April 21, 2019
How Zizek Should Have Replied
to Jordan Peterson
A missed opportunity to respond
to facile critiques of socialism…
If you had the misfortune of suffering
through the “debate” between Jordan Peterson and Slavoj Zizek, I offer you
my solidarity. Peterson and Zizek put on one of the most pathetic displays in
the history of intellectuals arguing with each other in public. This was not Foucault versus Chomsky or even Hitchens versus Hitchens. It almost makes the Bill Nye versus Ken Ham debate look good, and that’s really
saying something. Peterson and Zizek began with
long, 30-minute speeches, ostensibly on the subject of which system is more
conducive to human happiness—capitalism or socialism. The two speeches had virtually nothing
to do with each other and very little to do with the topic.
Peterson went
first. If you did high school debate, you know that this should have given
Zizek an advantage. He knows what Peterson has said, and in theory this should
enable him to reply to Peterson. But
instead, Zizek read a bizarre, meandering, canned speech which had very little
to do with anything Peterson said or with the assigned topic. This is a pity, because Peterson made an argument I have seen many times,
one which is incredibly easy to beat.
I teach politics at the
University of Cambridge, and we have this class called The Modern State
and Its Alternatives. One week, we have the students read The Communist
Manifesto along with a bunch of other texts on communism and socialism. My
students then write a 2,000 word paper in response to the prompt “Is socialism
a viable alternative to capitalism?” Most students write something interesting,
but every year a small number of people write what I call “the bad Marx paper.”
There are three necessary features which distinguish a bad Marx paper:
- The paper contains a close reading of the Manifesto.
- The paper contains almost no references to any other texts, either by Marx or by other socialist thinkers.
- The paper contains a long digression about all the reasons the Soviet Union was terrible. I call this the “tankie-bashing” bit.
It’s very clear
what has happened. The student read the Manifesto, because it is
short and doesn’t take very long. They didn’t read any other socialist texts.
Eventually, they ran out of things to say about the Manifesto and
filled up the rest of the word count with tankie bashing.
This is what Jordan Peterson did
with his half hour.
He starts by saying he read the Manifesto,
as all first year students do:
Alright, so, how did I prepare
for this? I went—I familiarized myself to the degree that it was possible, with
Slavoj Zizek’s work, and that wasn’t that possible because he has a lot of work
and he’s a very original thinker, and this debate was put together in
relatively short order. And what I did instead was return to what I regarded as
the original cause of all the trouble, let’s say, which was The
Communist Manifesto. And what I attempted to do—because that’s
Marx, and we’re here to talk about Marxism, let’s say—and, what I tried to do
was read it.
Peterson then claims to have picked out 10
claims in the Manifesto with which he disagreed. He doesn’t number them,
but
with some effort I think I managed to pick out the 10:
- History is to be viewed primarily as an economic class struggle. Peterson disagrees, because people have non-economic motivations. But he does admit that human beings are often hierarchical, and that hierarchies tend to concentrate power. Might we think of the rulers as one class and the non-rulers as another class?
- Peterson argues that Marxism doesn’t deal with natural scarcity, that we need hierarchy to deal with that. Fortunately for us, Peterson then claims that human hierarchies aren’t exploitative because that’s “unstable.” He doesn’t defend this assertion or engage with the Marxist conception of exploitation, presumably because he only read the Manifesto and neglected other work which clarifies it.
- History can be thought of as a binary class struggle, with clear divisions between the proletariat and the bourgeoisie. Peterson disagrees, because he thinks this division is unclear. He doesn’t engage with Marxist definitions of these terms, presumably because he only read the Manifesto and neglected other work which clarifies them, like G.A. Cohen’s Karl Marx’s Theory of History: A Defence. He claims that the Soviet-era deaths were caused by this lack of clarity—the first instance of tankie bashing. He also alleges Marx to be something of a Manichean, claiming that Marx views the bourgeoisie as “all-bad” and the proletariat as “all-good.” Peterson says this is why he doesn’t like identity politics. At no point in this is Peterson using any citations or quotes to support these claims. At least my students will make some effort to show how their interpretation is supported by the text.
- The notion of the “dictatorship of the proletariat.” Peterson says that Marx thinks this is a good idea because he thinks the proletariat is inherently good. Peterson says the proletariat can’t rule as a class, that certain members of the proletariat inevitably rule, and these people are corruptible. Marx himself is admittedly pretty vague about socialist political institutions. Many other socialists have more to say about them, like Eduard Bernstein, but Peterson only read the Manifesto and only seems interested in talking about Soviet-style institutions.
- Peterson now says that you can’t take a complicated system like the free market and replace it with a centralised mechanism without specifying how the people who run this centralised mechanism will be chosen. Again, other socialists have thought about this, and some socialists—like Janos Kornai and Alec Nove—want some level of decentralization, at least in some sectors. But Peterson didn’t read them, and apparently he hasn’t read them in his 56 years on the planet, despite repeatedly giving authoritative talks which purport to be about Marxism. He does not seem to have encountered the notion that you can be a socialist without being for unlimited centralization.
- Nothing the capitalists do counts as labour. Peterson admits that landed aristocrats don’t engage in labour, but he claims that people who run businesses are adding value as “managers.” He also claims that it doesn’t make sense for these managers to exploit their workers, because they would get more value out of the workers by not exploiting them. Peterson doesn’t see that attempting to get maximum value out of one’s workers is constitutive of exploitation for Marxists because Peterson hasn’t read enough Marxists to know how they use that term. He also doesn’t bother to engage with the Ehrenreichs’ work on the “professional-managerial class”, or “PMC.”
- Profit is theft. Peterson disagrees, arguing that because the managers add value, they are entitled to profit. But this isn’t what Marxists mean by “profit.” Profit is not the money the firm uses to pay the managers, it’s the money the firm uses to pay investors or to reinvest in the business. It’s tied to investment, not managerial compensation. The Marxist objection is not to investment per se—socialist states do a lot of investing—but to the exploitative relationships which bring that investment about. But Peterson didn’t read Cohen and the Ehrenreichs, so he doesn’t have a detailed picture. Peterson then makes an argument which vaguely appeals to the value profit has in sending price signals to producers, but lots of socialist models include price signaling mechanics—Nove discusses them at length.
- The proletariat will become “magically hyperproductive.” Peterson says he couldn’t figure out why Marx thinks socialism is more productive than capitalism. There are other theorists who have discussed the ways in which capitalism might begin to “fetter” the productive forces in ways which socialism could unleash—particularly Cohen—but Peterson doesn’t read them.
- Eventually this hyperproductivity will create a post-scarcity condition. Here Peterson briefly name-checks the theory of alienation, which has heretofore been left out, claiming that for Marx this is the point at which it becomes possible to do away with alienation through spontaneous creative work. Peterson thinks this creative work doesn’t suit everyone. Most socialists don’t share Marx’s notion of the perfect human life and envision a diverse array of cool things to do in their utopias, but say it with me: Peterson doesn’t read most socialists.
- Marx says that the capitalist system is, to this point, the most productive system. Peterson thinks this is Marx conceding the argument—if capitalism is the most productive system in history, why change it? This is the point in the talk where Peterson most clearly reveals his lack of engagement with the content of Marx’s theory of history. Marx thinks that each economic system is the most productive in history when first introduced, but that eventually each outlives its usefulness and is replaced by something more appropriate to the technology of the time. It’s at a point like this where I really wish Peterson would read Cohen’s Defence.
Peterson spends his remaining
time alleging that Marx’s theory led to a “special form of hell”—more tankie bashing—while claiming that all systems produce
inequality, but at least capitalism generates a lot of wealth.
The core issue with all of this
is that the Manifesto does not, by itself, provide the reader
with the full understanding of the different ways of interpreting Marxian
socialism—let alone all the other kinds of socialism that are out there these
days. This is why we don’t simply assign the Manifesto by itself. It is
accompanied by a
variety of additional texts, some of which are socialist and some of which
criticize the socialist project. Students who do the reading often
have interesting things to say about the viability of socialism, from multiple
ideological perspectives. I wouldn’t be writing this piece if Peterson produced
a thoughtful, critical engagement. The problem is that he is treated as a great
intellectual and invited to speak to large audiences about socialism when it’s
very clear he hasn’t read anything about it.
In my view, Marx makes three key
contributions to the history of thought, each of which has been further refined
and added to by those who have been influenced by him:
- The theory of alienation, which criticises capitalism for denying us the opportunity to be creative or to otherwise self-actualize.
- The theory of exploitation, which criticizes capitalism for forcing workers to surrender some of the value of what they produce by threatening them with starvation and homelessness.
- The theory of history, also known as “historical materialism,” “dialectical materialism,” and even “technological determinism,” which alleges that more competitive economic systems out-compete less competitive systems and that social structures, ideas, and cultures develop in a manner which serves to legitimate and support these economic system. In other words, the mode of production, or the “base,” determines the social relations, or the “superstructure.”
Peterson doesn’t seem to deny
that capitalism involves alienation and exploitation, but he sometimes
expresses uncertainty about how precisely exploitation works. To be clear, the
people who are exploited are the people who are compelled to work by the threat
of poverty. These are the wage-earners. The people who don’t have to work for a
living because they have enough resources to be idle might, in some cases, do
some work anyway. But if they are not being compelled to work, because they are
capable of living comfortably off their investments, they are people who live
off what they own rather than what they earn. This is
what separates the proletariat from the bourgeoisie. The proles earn wages, the
bourgeois own capital. There are some people—primarily professionals and
managers—who earn enough to retire and live off investments without the
assistance of a public or employer-funded pension scheme. These people are the
PMCs—the people the Ehrenreichs talk about. They do the actual work of managing
the economy and are given just enough that they will tend to help the truly
rich defend the system. But there’s a large gap between them and the wealthy.
Millionaires are not billionaires. Wilson Chandler, a middling NBA player for the LA Clippers, made
$12.8 million this year. He has a net worth of $35 million. He’s in the top 0.01 percent of the income
distribution. But he’s paid by Steve Ballmer, a man with a net worth of $46.5 billion. He spent
$2 billion just buying the team. Chandler’s net worth is 0.07 percent of
Ballmer’s net worth. Ballmer could employ more than 3600 Wilson Chandlers in a
year before he’d run out of wealth. Chandler is a professional. Ballmer is an owner.
But while Peterson evinces some
understanding of what the theories of alienation and exploitation are about, he
misses the theory of history completely. To start, Peterson thinks that Marx is
uninterested in humanity’s battle with nature. But this is precisely where the
theory of history begins. For Marx, we develop economic systems to meet our
material needs—to ensure we have the resources we need to survive. For Marx,
primitive economic systems—like chattel slavery, feudalism, and capitalism—rely
on the exploitation of human labor power to meet those needs. But eventually,
Marx hopes we can develop the technology necessary to end exploitation, and
even to overcome material scarcity itself. Peterson thinks Marx isn’t
interested in nature, but Marx’s theory of history is a theory of how human
beings might overcome nature.
Each economic system produces the
conditions necessary for its own obsolescence. When a society institutionalizes
slavery or feudalism, that makes it possible for some of the people in that
society to spend their time inventing new technologies that eventually make
industrialization possible. Once industrialization is possible, societies need
to be able to move their rural subjects to the cities and they need these
workers to be able to quickly move from job to job, filling in wherever the
new, fast-paced industrial economy needs them. Feudal peasants are tied to the
land. Slaves are tied to particular masters. Workers in employer/employee wage
relationships fit industrial capitalism better. So for Marx, the societies that
more quickly moved beyond feudalism and slavery were able to industrialize
faster, and the societies that moved more slowly needed to play catch-up or
face the threat of being colonized by their competitors. Eventually, Marx
thinks that capitalism will create new conditions that make even this
employer/employee relationship untenable. Different Marxists have different
views about when these “contradictions” will manifest or what they might look
like. Lenin thought socialism was the only thing that could put a stop to the
endless imperial
struggle that was World War I. More recently, Socialists have suggested automation,
climate
change, and neoliberal
acceleration might subject the system to new pressures the theorists of a
century ago could not anticipate, fettering capitalism in new ways and
unlocking the potential of new forms of socialism.
Marx’s theory is rather
Darwinian. The societies with more efficient economic systems subjugate and
exploit the societies that are less efficient. The only way to compete is for
the less efficient systems to copy their more efficient counterparts. So for
Marx, socialism can only happen if it is capable of beating capitalism at its
own game, of being more productive and more efficient than capitalism is.
Otherwise, the capitalists will subjugate socialist societies in much the same
way they subjugate feudal and tribal societies. This means that the theory of
history mandates that the conditions for socialism ought to first arise in the
most advanced capitalist states, where capitalism is most fully developed. But
no one ever tried socialism in the United States or Western Europe. Instead, it
was tried in poorer societies, like Russia, China, and many post-colonial
states. This wasn’t in keeping with the theory of history, and so in a very
real sense the ostensibly “Marxist” projects of the 20th century weren’t really
very Marxist.
Many socialists don’t like the
theory of history. They want to argue that socialism is possible in a wider
array of places, and they believe that ideas and culture have a larger role to
play in political change than historical materialism maintains. The fact that
socialism has yet to materialize in the richest and most powerful capitalist
states casts doubt on the theory, and the Frankfurt School socialists and their
successors—including Zizek—have argued that it is capitalist culture and
ideology which obstructs socialism in the west. Some of these socialists
position themselves as revisers of the theory of history while others position
themselves as its opponents. But some materialists continue to argue that
capitalism has yet to produce the changes in our technology, our environment,
and our political institutions which will eventually precipitate its collapse.
Why have employees when robots can do the work people could do? How can
capitalism be the most productive system, if it results in worldwide flooding
and the destruction of so many of the people and places it built? How can
capitalism sustain us if it kills the public services we rely on it to fund?
How can it make us feel safe and happy when it makes our jobs precarious?
It might have been interesting to hear what
Peterson thinks about automation, or climate change, or the austerity,
precarity, and atomization associated with our neoliberal hell world. But Zizek
didn’t push him to talk about these things, and Peterson doesn’t appear to have done
the reading that would be necessary for him to produce an interesting
conversation about them. Writing
in the 19th century, Marx was something of a prophet, a futurist—he was
imagining where capitalism might take us. But too often, when I see people
debate capitalism and socialism, they talk about the past. Imagine if, instead
of winding down feudalism and abolishing it in 1660, the British made the kinds
of arguments Peterson made in this debate. They might have pointed out that
feudalism made Britain richer than it had ever been before, that urban living
can be grim and brutal, that going to work in factories would rip families and
communities apart. And besides, don’t we care about other things aside from
economics? What about God and the church? Didn’t Saint Augustine tell us to
reject the city of man? Peterson celebrates a system his own arguments would
have defeated. As we stare down the barrel of climate change, anxious and
afraid, alone and isolated, perhaps some of us wish it had been so.
Such arguments were made by
conservatives in Britain for eons, before, during, and after the capitalist
transformation. The Lord of
the Rings is the film version, with Sauron and those industrious
orcs standing in for capitalism, and that copy-cat Saruman attempting to
destroy Sauron by adopting the same economic system and becoming just like him.
Tolkien is nostalgic for an imaginary medieval world full of good kings, merry
elves, and happy hobbits with full bellies.
In the old days, capitalists knew
they stood on perilous ground, facing fierce opposition from both the values of
yesterday and the values of tomorrow. As the capitalist system grows older, it
forgets its own story—the way it clawed and tore its way through the old feudal
aristocracy, with tea parties and guillotines. It is not natural. Like all
things, it has a lifespan. A century ago, during the 1924 U.K. General
Election, even the Liberal Party knew one day socialism lay ahead:
Are we still beyond it? And if not, what
comes next? How will capitalism handle all the messes it has created for us in
the next 100 years? These are the questions Zizek should have asked Peterson.
But he seems too sad and broken to try anymore. What’s the point of a socialist
who thinks capitalist ideology has us so thoroughly trapped that we cannot get
out? Not so long ago, Zizek compared ideology
to a pair of glasses that we must painfully remove to see the world clearly.
These days he seems to think we’ve all had LASIK.
Peterson didn’t prepare. There
was an opportunity. But Zizek was too busy complaining about
identity politics and his status within academia to try. He’s the sort of aging
quitter we all hope to never be.
If you appreciate our work,
please consider making a
donation, purchasing a
subscription, or supporting
our podcast on Patreon. Current Affairs is not for profit and carries no
outside advertising. We are an independent media institution funded entirely by
subscribers and small donors, and we depend on you in order to continue to
produce high-quality work.
Benjamin
Studebaker is a
PhD student at the University of Cambridge.
If you liked this article, you'll
love our print edition.
Subscribe today to Current Affairs magazine.
Subscribe today to Current Affairs magazine.
No comments:
Post a Comment