Introduction
On July 30, 1792, Kant wrote to
Johann Erich Biester, editor of the Berlinische
Monatsschrifi, requesting that he
return “as soon as possible” a manuscript, the four parts of which were to have
appeared in four successive issues of the journal (AK 11:336). The manuscript
was eventually published as Religion
within the Boundaries of Mere Reason. Biester had obtained the Berlin
censors’ imprimatur for the treatise that became Book I on religion but,
despite his appeal from their decision, had been firmly denied permission to
publish the treatise that became Book II. As Kant pointed out, the first
treatise, without the others, could cut an “odd figure” in the journal. In
place of it he offered to provide a strictly “moral” treatise, dealing with
Christian Garve’s criticism of Kant’s moral principle in Part I of his Essays on Various Topics from Morals, Literature
and Social Life (1792).
The treatise, as Kant first
described it, never appeared. Instead, the reply to Garve became Part I of Kant’s
essay “On the Common Saying: That May Be True in Theory, but It Is of No Use in
Practice,” which was published in the Berlinische
Monatsschrift in 1793. Since Garve’s criticism was, in part, that Kant’s
formal principle could not provide a motive for action, it could well be
brought under the “common saying.” So too could Kant’s contention against
Hobbes, in Part II, that subjects have noncoercive rights against their
sovereign, and his objection, in Part III, to Moses Mendelssohn’s view that the
human race will never make moral progress. As to why Kant chose to focus on
this common saying and extend it, there is no hard evidence. There is, however,
room for conjecture, especially with regard to Part II.
Kant’s interest in the French
Revolution, with its “Declaration of the Rights of Men and of Citizens” in
1789, was, of course, shared by others. Edmund Burke’s Reflections on the Revolution in France (1790) contemptuously
dismissed the subde “political metaphysics” of theorists who object to any
state not established on their principles. On the other hand, August Wilhelm
Rehberg’s Examination of the French Revolution, published at the beginning of
1793, declared that “metaphysics” had brought about the revolution, something
never heard of before. In his preliminary notes to the present essay (AK
23:127) Kant mentions the recent charge, never heard of before, that
metaphysics can cause a revolution, and questions whether this gives it
undeserved honor or undeserved blame, since “men of affairs” have long made it
their principle to banish metaphysics to the schools. Kant’s contention, here
as in Part I, is that metaphysics or a priori principles can be put into
practice. Although he denies that subjects have a right to rebel, he insists
upon a sovereign’s duty to give laws in conformity with their right to freedom,
equality, and independence and so to realize a civil society that approaches
reason’s idea of a civil union. The objection that this cannot be done is
based, like Garve’s, on the futile attempt to base theory on empirical grounds.
Of the three goals included in
the motto “Liberty, Equality, Fraternity,” the first two have traditionally
claimed the lion’s share of attention. Kant’s political writings are no
exception. In Part III of the present essay, however, Kant takes issue with
Moses Mendelssohn’s view that the human race will never make moral progress. If
this were the case, Kant maintains, we should be unable to fulfill our duty of
philanthropy. Although it need only be shown that the moral improvement of the
human race is not impossible, another essay, apparently written in 1795, finds evidence
of its improvement. Entitied “An Old Question Raised Again: Is the Human Race Constantly
Progressing?” it was published in 1798 as Part II of The Conflict of the Faculties. The next treatise in the present volume,
Toward Perpetual Peace, returns to
the political questions raised with regard to the “common saying.”
A sum of rules, even of
practical rules, is called theory if
those rules are thought as principles having a certain generality [Allgemeinheit], so that abstraction is made
from a multitude of conditions that yet have a necessary influence on their
application. Conversely, not every doing [Hantirung]
is called practice, but only that effecting
of an end which is thought as the observance of certain principles of procedure
represented in their generality.
It is obvious that between
theory and practice there is required, besides, a middle term connecting them
and providing a transition from one to the other, no matter how complete a
theory may be; for, to a concept of the understanding, which contains a rule,
must be added an act of judgment by which a practitioner distinguishes whether
or not something is a case of the rule; and since judgment cannot always be
given yet another rule by which to direct its subsumption (for this would go on
to infinity), there can be theoreticians who can never in their lives become
practical because they are lacking in judgment, for example, physicians or jurists
who did well during their schooling but who are at a loss when they have to
give an expert opinion. But even where this natural talent is present there can
still be a deficiency in premises, that is, a theory can be incomplete and can,
perhaps, be supplemented only by engaging in further experiments and
experiences, from which the recently schooled physician, agriculturalist, or
economist can and should abstract new rules for himself and make his theory
complete. In such cases it was not the fault of theory if it was of little use
in practice, but rather of there having been not enough theory, which the man in question should have learned
from experience and which is true theory even if he is not in a position to
state it himself and, as a teacher, set it forth systematically in general
propositions, and so can make no claim to the tide of theoretical physician,
agriculturalist and the like. Thus no one can pretend to be practically
proficient in a science and yet scorn theory without declaring that he is an
ignoramus in his field, inasmuch as he believes that by groping about in
experiments and experiences, without putting together certain principles (which
really constitute what is called theory) and without having thought out some
whole relevant to his business [ein
Ganzes ... über sein Geschäft] (which, if one proceeds methodically in it,
is called a system), he can get further than theory could take him.
Yet it is easier to put up with
an ignorant man who declares that theory is unnecessary and dispensable in his
supposed practice than with a would-be expert who concedes it and its value in
schools (perhaps only to exercise the mind) but at the same time maintains that
matters are quite different in practice; that when one goes from school into the
world one becomes aware that one has been pursuing empty ideals and philosophic
dreams; in short, that what sounds good in theory has no validity for practice.
(This is often expressed as, this or that proposition does indeed hold in thesi,
but not in hypothesi.) Now if an
empirical engineer tried to disparage general mechanics, or an artilleryman the
mathematical doctrine of ballistics, by saying that whereas the theory of it is
nicely thought out it is not valid in practice since, when it comes to application,
experience yields quite different results than theory, one would merely laugh
at him (for, if the theory of friction were added to the first and the theory
of the resistance of air to the second, hence if only still more theory were added,
these would accord very well with experience). However, it is quite different
with a theory having to do with objects of intuition than with a theory in
which objects are represented only by means of concepts (with objects of
mathematics and objects of philosophy); the latter objects could perhaps be thought quite well and irreproachably
(on the part of reason), but perhaps they could not be given at all but might well be mere empty ideas, of which either no
use at all would be made in practice or even a use that would be detrimental to
it. That common saying could, therefore, still be correct in such cases.
But in a theory that is based
on the concept of duty, concern about
the empty ideality of this concept quite disappears. For it would not be a duty
to aim at a certain effect of our will if this effect were not also possible in
experience (whether it be thought as completed or as always approaching completion);
and it is theory of this kind only that is at issue in the present treatise.
For, to the scandal of philosophy, it is not uncommonly alleged of this theory
that what may be correct in it is yet invalid in practice; and this is said in
a lofty, disdainful tone, full of the presumption of wanting to reform reason
by experience even in that in which reason puts its highest honor, and in a wisdom
that can see farther and more clearly with its dim moles’ eyes fixed on
experience than with the eyes belonging to a being that was made to stand erect
and look at the heavens.
This maxim, which has become
very common in our times, so full of talk and empty of deeds, does the greatest
harm when it has to do with something moral (duties of virtue or duties of right).
For here it is a matter of the canon of reason (in the practical), where the
worth of practice rests entirely on its conformity with the theory underlying
it, and all is lost if the empirical and hence contingent conditions of
carrying out the law are made conditions of the law itself, so that a practice
calculated with reference to an outcome probable in accordance with previous experience is given authority
to control a self-sufficient theory.
I divide this treatise
according to the three different standpoints from which the worthy gentleman who
so boldly disparages theories and systems usually appraises his objects, and so
in his three capacities [in dreifacher
Qualität] i) as a private individual who is still a man of affairs, 2) as a statesman, 3) as a man of the world (or citizen of the world generally). These three
persons are at one in attacking the academic,
who works on theory on behalf of them all and for their benefit; since they
fancy that they understand matters better than he, they seek to banish him to
his school (ilia se iactet in aula!),
[Let him lord it there in his own court! Virgil Aeneid 1.140.] as a scholar who, spoiled for practice, only stands
in the way of their experienced wisdom.
We shall therefore present the
relation of theory to practice in three parts: first in Morals [Moral. Although I have translated Moral throughout this essay as “morals,”
in some passages Kant uses it in the sense of “moral philosophy.”] generally
(with a view to the well-being [das Wohl]
of every human being), second in politics (with reference to the
well-being of states), third from a cosmopolitan perspective (with a view to the well-being of the human race as a whole and insofar as it is conceived as progressing
toward its well-being in the series of generations of all future times). The
tides of the parts will, on grounds arising from the treatise itself, be
expressed as the relation of theory to practice in morals, in the right of a state,
and in the right of nations.
I. ON THE RELATION OF THEORY OF
PRACTICE IN MORALS GENERALLY (In reply to some objections by Professor Garve*)
[* Versuche über verschiedne Gegenstände aus der Moral und Literatur, von Ch. Garve. Erster Theil, S. III bis
116. [Essays on Various Topics from
Morals and Literature, by Christian Garve, Part I, pp. 111—16]. I call this
worthy man’s contesting of my propositions objections
to matters in which (as I hope) he wishes to reach agreement with me, not
attacks, which, as disparaging assertions, should provoke a defense; this is
not the place to defend them nor am I inclined to do so here.]
Before I come to the real point
of controversy over what, in the use of one and the same concept, may be valid
in theory only or in practice, I must compare my theory, as I have elsewhere
represented it, with the representation of it that Garve gives, in order to see
in advance whether we even understand each other.
A. I explained morals
provisionally as the introduction to a science that teaches, not how we are to
become happy, but how we are to become worthy of happiness.* In doing so I did
not fail to remark that the human being is not thereby required to renounce his natural end, happiness,
when it is a matter of complying with his duty; for that he cannot do, just as
no finite rational being whatever can; instead, he must abstract altogether from this consideration when the command of
duty arises; he must on no account make it the condition of his comphance with the law prescribed to him by
reason; indeed he must, as far as is possible for him, strive to become aware
that no incentive derived from that
gets mixed, unnoticed, into the determination of duty, and this is effected by
his representing duty as connected with the sacrifices its observance (virtue)
costs us rather than with the advantages it yields us, so as to represent the
command of duty in all its authority, as requiring unconditional obedience,
sufficient in itself and in need of no other influences.
[* Worthiness to be happy is
that quality of a person, based upon the subject’s own will, such that a reason
giving universal laws (for nature as well as for free will) would harmonize
with all the ends of this person. It is therefore quite different from skill in
acquiring some happiness. [ein Glück]
For he is not even worthy of this skill and of the talents nature has lent him
for it if he has a will which does not harmonize with that will which alone is
adapted to a universal legislation of reason and which cannot be included in it
(i.e., which conflicts with morality).]
a. Now, the way Garve expresses
this proposition of mine is that “I had maintained that observance of the moral
law, without any regard for happiness at all, is the sole final end for the human being, that is must be
considered the creator’s sole end.” (According to my theory, neither human
morality by itself nor human happiness by itself is the creator’s sole end, but
rather the highest good possible in the world, which consists of the union and
harmony of the two.)
B. I remarked further that this
concept of duty does not have to be grounded on any particular end but rather introduces another end for the human
being’s will, namely to work to the best of one’s ability [nach allem Vermög] toward the highest
good possible in the world (universal happiness combined with and in
conformity with the purest morality throughout the world), which, since it is
within our control from one quarter but not from both taken together, exacts
from reason belief, for practical purposes, in a moral ruler of the world and in a future life. It is
not as if the universal concept of duty first gets “support and stability” only
on the presupposition of both, that is, gets a sure basis and the requisite
strength of an incentive, but rather
that only in that ideal of pure reason does it also get an object.* For, in itself duty is nothing other than the limitations of the will to the condition
of a giving of universal law possible through a maxim adopted, whatever the object
of the will or the end may be (thus happiness as well), from which, as well as
from every end one may have, we here abstract altogether. In the question of
the principle of morals the doctrine
of the highest good, as the final end of a will determined by this doctrine and
conformed with its laws, can be completely passed over and set aside (as
episodic); and it will also become apparent in what follows, when it comes to
the real point of controversy, that this is not taken into consideration at all
but only morals in general.
[*The need to assume, as the
final end of all things, a good that is the highest
good in the world and also possible
through our cooperation is a need [arising] not from a deficiency in moral
incentives but from a deficiency in the external relations within which alone
an object as end in itself (as moral final
end) can be produced in conformity
with these incentives. For without some end there can be no will, although, if it is a question only
of lawful necessitation of actions, one must abstract from any end and the law
alone constitutes its determining ground. But not every end is moral (e.g.,
that of one’s own happiness is not), but this must rather be an unselfish one;
and the need for a final end assigned by pure reason and comprehending the
whole of all ends under one principle (a world as the highest good and possible
through our cooperation) is a need of an unselfish will extending itself beyond observance of the formal law to production
of an object (the highest good). This is a special kind of determination of the
will, namely through the idea of the whole of all ends, the basis of which is
that if we stand in certain moral
relations to things in the world we must everywhere obey the moral law, and
beyond this there is added the duty to bring it about as far as we can that such a relation (a world in keeping
with the moral highest ends) exists. In this the human being thinks of himself
by analogy with the Deity who, although subjectively in need of no external
thing, still cannot be thought to shut himself up within himself but rather to
be determined to produce the highest good beyond himself just by his
consciousness of his complete self-sufficiency; and this necessity in the
supreme being (which in the human being is a duty) can be represented by us only as a moral need. With the human
being too, accordingly, the incentive which is present in the idea of the
highest good possible in the world by his cooperation is not his own happiness
thereby intended but only this idea as end in itself, and hence compliance with
it as duty. For it contains no prospect of happiness absolutely, but only of a
proportion between it and the worthiness of a subject, whatever that may be.
But a determination of will which limits itself and its aim of belonging to
such a whole to this condition is not
selfish.]
b. Garve expresses this
proposition as follows: “that the virtuous person can never lose sight of that
perspective (his own happiness) nor may he do so, since otherwise he would lose
altogether passage into the invisible world, to conviction of the existence of
God and of immortality, which is yet, according to this theory, absolutely
necessary to give the moral system
support and stability”; and he then concludes by briefly summing up the
assertions he attributes to me: “The virtuous person, according to those
principles, strives unceasingly to be worthy of happiness but never, insofar as he is truly virtuous, to be happy.” (The words insofar as create an ambiguity here, which must be settled at the outset.
They can mean, in the act by which,
as virtuous he subjects himself to his duty, in which case this proposition is perfectly
in accord with my theory. Or they can mean that just by his being virtuous
generally, and so even when it is not a matter of duty and there would be no
conflict with it, a virtuous person should still have no regard at all for
happiness; and this quite contradicts my assertions.)
These objections are therefore
nothing but misunderstandings (for I do not care to take them as
misrepresentations), and their possibility would have to be astonishing, did
not the human propensity to follow one’s accustomed course of thought even in
appraising the thoughts of others, and thus to carry the former over into the
latter, adequately explain such a phenomenon.
Upon this polemical treatment
of the above moral principle there now follows a dogmatic assertion of the
opposite. Garve concludes analytically as follows: “In the ordering of concepts, perception and distinction of states
[Zustande. In Part I of this essay,
where there is no need to distinguish Zustand
from Staat, Zustand in translated as “state.”], whereby one of them is given preference over the other, must precede
the choice [Wahl] of one of them and
hence the determination in advance [Voraushestimmung]
of a certain end. But a state that a being endowed with consciousness of himself
and of his state prefers to other
ways of being, when this state is present and perceived by him, is a good state; and a series of such good states
is the most general concept expressed by the word happiness.” Further, “A law supposes motives, while motives suppose
an already perceived distinction of a worse state from a better one. This
perceived distinction is the element of the concept of happiness, and so forth.”
Further, “From happiness in the most general sense of the word arises the motives for every
effort and so too for observance of
the moral law. I must first know in general that something is good before I can
ask whether fulfillment of moral duties belongs under the heading of the good;
the human being must have an incentive,
which puts him in motion, before one can
set him a goal,* toward which this
motion is to be directed.”
[*This is precisely what I
insist upon. The incentive which the human being can have before a goal (end) is
set for him can obviously be nothing other than the law itself through the
respect that it inspires (without its being determined what end one may have
and may attain by complying with it). For the law with respect to what is
formal in choice is indeed all that remains when I have left out of
consideration the matter of choice (the goal, as Garve calls it).]
This argument is nothing more
than a play upon the ambiguity of the word the
good; for this [can be taken to mean] either what is good in itself and
unconditionally, as opposed to what is evil in itself, or else what is only conditionally
good, as compared with what is a lesser or greater good, since the state chosen
[der Zustand der Wahl] in the latter
case can be a state that is relatively better but in itself evil. The maxim of
unconditional observance of a categorically commanding law of free choice [der freien Willkür] (i.e., of duty), without
having regard for any end at all put at its basis, is essentially different,
that is, different in kind, from the maxim in which the motive for acting in a certain
way is to pursue the end assigned us by nature itself (which is called
happiness in general). For the first maxim is in itself good, the second by no
means; in case of a collision with duty it can be quite evil. On the other
hand, if a certain end is laid down as a basis, so that no law commands
unconditionally (but only under the condition of this end), then two opposing
actions can both be conditionally good but one better than the other (the latter of which could then be called
relatively evil); for they are different from each other not in kind
but merely in degree. And this is how it is with all actions the motive of which
is not the unconditional law of reason (duty) but an end that we have by choice
[willkürlich] made their basis; for
this belongs to the sum of all ends the attainment of which is called
happiness, and one action can contribute more, another less to my happiness and
so be better or worse than the other. But the preference of one state of determination of the will to another is
merely an act of freedom (res merae facultatis, as jurists say), in regard to which no account at all
is taken of whether this (determination of the will) is good or evil in itself,
and is thus indifferent with respect to both.
A state of being bound up with
a certain given end that I prefer to any other of
the same kind is a relatively better state, namely in the sphere of happiness
(which is recognized by reason as good only conditionally, so far as one
is worthy of it). But that state in which I am aware that, in case of a collision
of certain of my ends with the moral law of duty, I prefer the latter is not
merely a better state but the only one that is good in itself; it is a good
from another sphere altogether, where ends that may present themselves to me
(and so too their sum, happiness) are not taken into consideration at all and
where it is not the matter of choice (an object put at its basis) but the mere
form of the universal lawfulness of its maxims that constitutes its determining
ground. Thus it can by no means be said that I account to my happiness any
state that I prefer to be in than any
other kind. For I must first be sure that I am not acting against my duty; only
afterwards am I permitted to look around for happiness, to the extent that I
can unite the state of being happy with that morally (not naturally) good state
of mine.*
[* Happiness contains all (and
also not more than) that which nature provides us; but virtue contains what no
one other than the human being can give himself or take away from himself. If
someone wanted to retort that by deviating from the latter a human being can at
least bring upon himself reproach and purely moral self-censure and hence
dissatisfaction, so that he can make himself unhappy, that may certainly be
granted. But only a virtuous man or one who is on his way to being virtuous is
susceptible to [fähig] this purely
moral dissatisfaction (not from disadvantageous results of his action but from
its unlawfulness itself). His dissatisfaction is consequently not the cause but
only the effect of his being virtuous; and the motive for being virtuous could
not be derived from such unhappiness (if one wants to give this name to the
pain resulting from a misdeed).]
Certainly, the will must have motives; but these are not certain
objects proposed as ends related to natural
feeling, but nothing other than the unconditional law itself; and the will’s receptivity to finding itself subject to
the law as unconditional necessitation is called moral feeling, which is therefore
not the cause but the effect of the determination of the will, and we would not
have the least perception of it within ourselves if that necessitation were not
already present within us. Thus the old refrain, that this feeling and hence a
pleasure that we make an end for ourselves is the first cause of the
determination of the will, so that happiness (to which it belongs as an
element) still constitutes the basis of all objective necessity in acting and
hence of all obligation, is a piece of sophistical trifling [unter die
vernünftelnden Tändelein gehört] That is to say, if one cannot cease
asking, even after 3 cause has been cited for a certain effect, one finally
makes the effect its own cause.
I now come to the point that
really concerns us here, namely to illustrate with examples and to test the
supposed conflicting interests of theory and of practice in philosophy. Garve
gives the best example of it in his treatise cited above. He says first
(speaking of the distinction I find between a doctrine of how we are to become happy and one of how we are to become worthy of happiness): “For my own part,
I confess that I very well conceive this division of ideas in my head, but that I do not find this division
of wishes and strivings in my heart, and
that it is even inconceivable to me how any one can become aware of having
detached himself altogether from his desire for happiness and hence aware of
having performed his duty quite unselfishly.”
I shall first reply to the
latter. I readily grant that no one can become aware with certainty of having performed his duty quite unselfishly;
for that belongs to inner experience, and to this consciousness of his state of
soul there would have to belong a perfectly clear representation of all the associated
representations [Nebenvorstellungen] and
considerations attached to the concept of duty by imagination, habit, and
inclination, which cannot be required in any case; and, in general, the
nonexistence of something (and so too of a covertly thought advantage) cannot
be an object of experience. But that the human being ought to perform his duty quite unselfishly and that he must altogether
separate his craving for happiness from the concept of duty, in order to have
this concept quite pure: ofthat he is aware with the utmost clarity or, should
he believe that he is not, it can be required of him that he be so, as far as
he can; for the true worth of morality is to be found precisely in this purity,
and he must therefore also be capable of it. Perhaps no one has ever performed
quite unselfishly (without admixture of other incentives) the duty he cognizes
and also reveres; perhaps no one will ever succeed in doing so, however hard he
tries. But insofar as, in examining himself most carefully, he can perceive not
only no such cooperating motive but instead self-denial with respect to many
motives oppos
ing the idea of duty, he can become aware of a maxim of striving for
such purity; that he is capable of, and that is also sufficient for his
observance of duty. On the other hand, to make it his maxim to foster the
influence of such motives, on the pretext that human nature does not admit of
such purity (though this, again, he cannot assert with certainty) is the death
of all morality.
As for
Garve’s avowal, just cited, that he does not find such a division (strictly
speaking, separation) in his heart, I
have no hesitation in contradicting his self-accusation outright and in
championing his heart against his head.
He, a man of integrity, has actually found
this separation in his heart every time (in his determination of will), only it
would not be reconciled in his head * - for the sake of speculation and of
comprehending what is incomprehensible (inexplicable), namely the possibility
of categorical imperatives (such as those of duty are) with the usual
principles oi psychological explanation (all of which have the mechanism of
natural necessity as their basis).
[* Professor Garve (in his
notes to Cicero’s book on duties [De Officis],
1783 edition, p. 69) makes the following admission, notable and worthy of his
acuteness: “Freedom, according to his innermost conviction, will always remain
unresolved and will never be explained.” A proof of its reality can absolutely
not be found either in an immediate or in a mediate experience; and yet one
also cannot accept it without any proof since a proof of its reality cannot be
derived from merely theoretical grounds (for these would have to be sought in
experience) and must therefore be derived from practical rational propositions
only but not from technically practical ones (since these would in turn require
experiential grounds) and can consequendy be derived only from morally
practical propositions, one has to wonder why Garve did not have recourse to
the concept of freedom, so as at least to save the possibility of such
imperatives.]
But I must loudly and zealously
contradict Garve when he concludes by saying: “Such fine distinctions among
ideas already become obscure in reflecting upon particular objects; but
they disappear completely when it comes to acting,
when they are to be applied to desires and purposes. The more simple, rapid and
stripped of clear representations is the step by which we
pass from considering motives to actually acting, so much the less is it possible
to cognize precisely and surely the determinate weight that each motive
contributed to guiding the step in this and in no other way.”
The concept of duty in its
complete purity is not only incomparably simpler, clearer and, for practical
use, more readily grasped and more natural to everyone than any motive derived
from happiness, or mixed with it and with regard for it (which always requires
much art [Kunst] and reflection); it
is also, even in the judgment of the most common human reason if only the
concept is presented in its purity to a human will, separated from and even in
opposition to the latter - far more powerful,
forceful, and promising of results than all motives borrowed from the latter,
selfish principle. Take the case, for example, that someone is holding in trust
something belonging to another (depositum),
the owner of which has died, and that the owner’s heirs know nothing about it
and can never come to know of it. We submit this case
even to a child some eight or nine years old, and add that the holder of this
deposit suffers at this very time (through no fault of his own) a complete
reversal of his fortune and sees around him a miserable family of vdfe and
children oppressed by want that he could relieve in a moment by appropriating
this deposit; we add further that he is philanthropic and beneficent whereas
those heirs are wealthy, hard-hearted and, besides, so thoroughly given to luxury
and wastefulness that adding anything to their resources would be equivalent to
throwing it into the sea. And we now ask whether, under such circumstances, it
can be considered permissible for him to put this deposit to his own use. The
one being questioned will undoubtedly answer, No! and, in place of any grounds,
will be able to say only, It is wrong!
that is, it conflicts with duty. Nothing is clearer than this, though it is
surely not clear that the trustee would be furthering his own happiness by giving up the deposit. For,
if he expected to determine his decision in view of the latter he could, for
example, think as follows: “If you give up the other’s goods you have to the
true owners without being called upon to do so, they will presumably reward you
for your honesty; or if that does not happen, you will acquire a good
reputation at large, which can be very lucrative. But all this is most
uncertain. Many doubts also arise about the opposite course: If you embezzle
the deposit so as to get out of your depressed circumstances at one stroke, by
making quick use of it you will incur suspicion as to how and by what means you
had so soon bettered your circumstances; but if you put it to work slowly, your
poverty will meanwhile increase so much it would come to be beyond remedy.” By
the maxim of happiness a will thus vacillates between its incentives as to what
it should decide upon; for it looks to the outcome and this is highly
uncertain; a good head is required to find a way out of the crush of arguments
and counterarguments without cheating oneself in the total reckoning. On the
other hand, if he asks himself what his duty is in this matter, he is not at
all perplexed about what answer to give but certain on the spot what he has to
do. He even feels, if the concept of duty counts for something with him, a
revulsion merely at calculating the advantages he could gain by transgressing
it, as if he still had a choice’ in the matter.
That these distinctions (which,
as we have just shown, are not so fine as Garve thinks but are inscribed on the
human soul in the broadest and most legible characters), as he says, disappear altogether when it comes to acting thus contradicts even his own
experience. Admittedly, it does not contradict the experience that the history of maxims drawn from the one or the
other principle presents; such experience proves, regrettably, that maxims for
the most part flow from the latter principle (of selfishness); but it does
contradict the experience, which can only be inward, [innerlich] that no idea so elevates the human mind and animates it
even to inspiration as that of a pure moral disposition, revering duty above
all else, struggling with the coundess ills of life and even with its most
seductive allurements and yet overcoming them (as we may rightlsy assume that
one is capable of doing). That the human being is aware that he can do this
because he ought to disclose within him a depth of divine predispositions and
lets him feel, as it were, a holy awe at the greatness and sublimity of his
true vocation. And if this attention were drawn to it more often and he became used
to ridding virtue completely of all the rich booty of advantages to be amassed
through the observance of duty and to representing it in all its purity; if it
became a principle of private and public instruction always to make use of this
(a method of inculcating duties that has almost always been neglected), human
morality would soon be better off that historical experience up to now has
still not proved the success of the doctrine of virtue may well be the fault of
just the false presupposition that the incentive derived from the idea of duty
in itself is much too fine for the common concept whereas the coarser incentive
drawn from certain advantages to be expected, in this world or even in a future
one, from compliance with the law (without regard for the law itself as the
incentive) would work more powerfully on the mind, and that up to now it has
been made a principle of education and homiletics to give preference to the
aspiration for happiness over that which reason makes the supreme condition of this,
namely worthiness to be happy. For precepts
as to how one can make oneself happy or at least avoid what is disadvantageous
are not commands. They do not bind
anyone absolutely; having been warned, one may choose [wählen] what he thinks good, if he is prepared to suffer the
consequences. He has no cause to regard as punishments such troubles as might
issue from his failure to follow the advice he was given; for punishments
happen only to a will that is free but contrary to the law; nature and
inclination, however, cannot give laws to freedom. It is quite different with
the idea of duty, someone’s transgression of which, even without his
considering the disadvantages to himself resulting from it, works immediately
upon his mind and makes him reprehensible and punishable in his own eyes.
Here, then, is a clear proof
that everything in moral philosophy that is correct for theory must also hold
for practice. Everyone in his capacity as a human being, a being subjected by
his own reason to certain duties, is accordingly a man of affairs; and since, as a man, he never outgrows the school
of wisdom, he cannot with proud contempt, as someone supposedly better
instructed by experience about what a human being is and what can be required
of him, send the adherent of theory back to school. For all this experience
does not help him at all to escape the precept of theory, but at most only
helps him to learn how theory could be better and more generally put to work,
after one has adopted it into one’s principles; but we are not speaking here of
such pragmatic skill but only of principles.
II. ON THE RELATION OF THEORY
TO PRACTICE IN THE RIGHT OF A STATE (Against Hobbes)
Among all the contracts by
which a multitude of people unites into a society (pactum sociale), the contract establishing a civil constitution among
them (pactum unionis civilis) is of
such a distinctive kind that, although with respect to its application [Ausführung] it has much in common with
any other (which is likewise directed to some discretionary [beliebigen] end to be promoted by common
effort), it is essentially different from every other in the principle of its institution
(constitutionis civilis). The union
of many for some (common) end (that all of them have) is to be found in any social contract; but that union which
is in itself an end (that each ought to
have) and which is therefore the unconditional and first duty in any
external relation of people in general, who cannot help mutually affecting one
another, is to be found in a society only insofar as it is in the civil
condition [Zustand], that is, constitutes
a commonwealth. Now the end that, in such an external relation, is in itself
duty and even the supreme formal condition [Bedingung]
(conditio sine qua non) of all other
external duties is the right of human
beings under public coercive laws, by
which what belongs to each can be determined for him and secured against
encroachment by any other.
But the concept of an external
right as such proceeds entirely from the concept of freedom in the external relation of people to one another and has
nothing at all to do with the end that all of them naturally have (their aim of
happiness) and with the prescribing of means for attaining it; hence too the
latter absolutely must not intrude in the laws of the former as their determining
ground. Right is the limitation of
the freedom of each to the condition of its harmony with the freedom of
everyone insofar as this is possible in accordance with a universal law; and public right is the sum of external laws
which make such a thoroughgoing harmony possible. Now, since any limitation of freedom through another’s choice [Willkür] is called coercion, it follows
that a civil constitution is a relation oi free
human beings who (without prejudice to their freedom within the whole of their
union with one another) are nevertheless subject to coercive laws; for reason itself
wills it so, and indeed pure reason giving laws a priori, which has no regard
for any empirical ends (all of which are comprehended under the general name
happiness); for, since people differ in their thinking about happiness and how
each would have it constituted, their wills with respect to it cannot be
brought under any common principle and so under any external law harmonizing
with everyone’s freedom.
Thus the civil condition,
regarded merely as a rightful condition, is based a priori on the following
principles:
1. The freedom of every member of the society as a human being.
2. His equality with every other as a subject.
3. The independence of every member of a commonwealth as a citizen.
These principles are not so
much laws given by a state already established as rather principles in
accordance with which alone the establishment of a state is possible in
conformity with pure rational principles of external human right. Accordingly,
I. As for the freedom [of every member of a state] as
a human being I express its principle for the constitution of a commonwealth in
the following formula: No one can coerce me to be happy in his way (as he
thinks of the welfare [Wohlsein] of
other human beings); instead, each may seek his happiness in the way that seems
good to him, provided he does not infringe upon that freedom of others to
strive for a like end which can coexist with the freedom of everyone in
accordance with a possible universal law (i.e., does not infringe upon this
right of another). A government established on the principle of benevolence
toward the people like that of a father
toward his children that is, a paternalistic government (imperium patemale),
in which the subjects, like minor children who cannot distinguish between what
is truly useful or harmful to them, are constrained to behave only passively,
so as to wait only upon the judgment of the head of state as to how they should be happy and, as for his also willing
their happiness, only upon his kindness is the greatest despotism thinkable (a constitution that abrogates all the freedom
of the subjects, who in that case have no rights at all). Not a paternalistic but a patriotic government (imperium
non patemale, sedpatrioticum) is
the only one that can be thought for human beings, who are capable [fähig] of rights, and also with
reference to the benevolence of the ruler. In a patriotic way of thinking everyone in a state (its head not
excepted) regards the commonwealth as the maternal womb, or the country as the paternal
land, from which and on which he has arisen and which he must also leave behind
as a cherished pledge, only so as to consider himself authorized to protect its
rights by laws of the common will but not to subject the use of it to his nconditional
discretion. This right of freedom belongs to him, a member of a commonwealth,
as a human being namely insofar as he is a being that is, as such, capable of
rights.
2. The equality [of each member of a state] as a subject, the formula of which
can read: Each member of a commonwealth has coercive rights against every
other, the only exception being the head of state (since he is not a member of
the commonwealth but its creator or preserver), who alone is authorized to
coerce without himself being subject to a coercive law. But whoever is subject to laws [unter Gesetzen steht]
is a subject [Untertan] within a
state and is thus subjected [unterworfen]
to coercive right equally with all the other members of the commonwealth; only
one (physical or moral person), the head of state, by whom alone any rightful
coercion can be exercised, is excepted. For if he could also be coerced he
would not be the head of state and the sequence of subordination would ascend
to infinity. But if there were two of them (uncoercible persons), neither would
be subject to coercive laws and one could do the other no wrong; and that is
impossible.
But this thoroughgoing equality
of individuals within a state, as its subjects, it quite consistent with the
greatest inequality in terms of the quantity and degree of their possessions,
whether in physical or mental superiority over others or in external goods [Glücksgütern] and in rights generally
(of which there can be many) relatively to others; thus the welfare of one is very
much dependent upon the will of another (that of the poor on the rich); thus
one must obey (as a child its elders or a wife her husband) and the other
directs; thus one serves (a day laborer) and the other pays him, and so forth.
But in terms of right (which, as the
expression of the general will, can be only one and which concerns the form of
what is laid down as right [Rechtens]
not the matter or the object in which I have a right), they are nevertheless
all equal to one another as subjects; for, no one of them can coerce any other
except through public law (and its executor, the head of state), through which
every other also resists him in like measure; but no one can lose this
authorization to coerce (and so to have a right against others) except by his
own crime, and he cannot give it away of his own accord, that is, by a
contract, and so bring it about by a rightful action [rechtliche Handlung] that he has no rights but only duties; for he
would thereby deprive himself of the right to make a contract and thus the
contract would nullify itself.
From this idea of the equality
of human beings as subjects within a commonwealth there also issues the
following formula; Every member of a commonwealth must be allowed to attain any
level of rank within it (that can belong to a subject) to which his talent, his
industry and his luck can take him; and his fellow subjects may not stand in
his way by means of a hereditary prerogative
(privileges [reserved] for a certain rank), so as to keep him and his
descendants forever beneath the rank.
For all right consists merely
in the limitation of the freedom of every other to the condition [Bedingung] that it can coexist with my
freedom in accordance with a universal law, and public right (within a
commonwealth) is merely the condition [Zustand]
of an actual legislation in conformity with this principle and joined with
power, by virtue of which all those belonging to a people as subjects are in a
rightful condition (status iuridicus)
as such, namely a condition of equality of action and reaction of a choice limiting
one another [einer ... einander
einschränkenden Willkür] in conformity with a universal law of freedom
(which is called the civil condition); hence the innate right of each in
this condition (i.e., his right prior to any rightful deed) is altogether equal with respect to the authorization
to coerce every other to remain always within the bounds of the consistency of
the use of his freedom with mine. Now since birth is not a deed of the one who is born, he cannot incur by it any inequality
of rightful condition and any other subjection to coercive laws than merely that
which is common to him along with all others, as subjects of the sole supreme
legislative power; hence there can be no innate prerogative of one member of a
commonwealth over another as fellow subjects, and no one can bequeath to his
descendants the prerogative of the rank
which he has within a commonwealth and so also cannot, as if qualified by birth
for the ruling rank, coercively prevent others from attaining by their own merit
the higher levels of subordination (of superior
and inferior, in which no one,
however, is imperans and the other subiectus). He may bequeath anything
else, whatever is a thing (not pertaining to personality) and can be acquired
as property and also alienated by him, and so in a series of generations
produce a considerable inequality of financial circumstances among the members
of a commonwealth (of hireling and hirer, landowners [Gutseigentümers] and agricultural laborers, and so forth); but he
may not prevent their being authorized to raise themselves to like
circumstances if their talent, their industry, and their luck make this
possible for them. For otherwise he could coerce without others in turn being
able to coerce him by their reaction, and would rise above the level of a fellow
subject. Again, no one living in a rightful condition of a commonwealth can
fall from this equality otherwise than by his own crime, never by a contract or
by military force (occupatio bellica);
for he cannot, by means of any rightful deed (whether his own or another’s)
cease to be in rightful possession of himself [Eigner seiner selbst zu sein] and enter the class of domestic
animals, which are used for any service as one wants and are kept in it without
their consent as long as one wants, even though with the restriction (sometimes
sanctioned by religion, as with the Indians) not to maim or kill them. He can
be considered happy [für glücklich]
in that condition provided he is aware that, if he does not reach the same
level as others, the fault lies only in himself ([his lack of] ability or
earnest will) or in circumstances for which he cannot blame any other, but not
in the irresistible will of others who, as his fellow subjects in this
condition, have no advantage over him as far as right is concerned.*
[* If we want to connect with
the word gracious a determinate
concept (distinct from kind, beneficent, protective and the like), it can be
assigned only to him against whom there is no coercive right. Hence only the
head of public administration [Staatsverwaltung]
who brings about and bestows whatever good is possible in accordance with
public laws (for the sovereign, which
gives laws, is, as it were invisible; it is the personified law itself, not its
agent) can be entitled gracious lord, as the only one against whom there
is no coercive right. So even in an aristocracy, as in Venice, for example, the
Senate is the only gracious lord; all
the nobles who comprise it, not excluding the Doge himself, are subjects (for only the Grand Coundl is the
sovereign) and, as far as the exercise of right [Rechtsausühung] is concerned, are equal to all others, that is a
coercive right against each of them belongs to a subject. Princes (i.e.,
persons to whom there belongs a hereditary right to government) are, however,
called gracious lords (by courtly etiquette, par courtoisie) only
prospectively and because of that claim; but in terms of their status of
possession [Besitzstand] they are
still fellow subjects, and even the least of their servants must have a
coercive right against them by means of the head of state. Thus there can be no
more than a single gracious lord within a state. But as for gracious (strictly
speaking, distinguished) ladies, they can be regarded as justified [in their claim
to] this title by their rank together
with their sex (thus only against the male
sex), and this by virtue of a
refinement of manners [Sitten]
(called gallantry) by which the male sex believes that it honors itself in
proportion as it grants the fair sex precedence over itself.]
3. The independence (sibisufficentia)
of a member of a state as a citizen, that
is, as a colegislator. As for legislation itself, it is not the case that all who
are free and equal under already existing public laws are to be held equal with
regard to the right to give these laws. Those who are not qualified [fähig] for this right are still, as
members of the commonwealth, subject to compliance with these laws and thereby
enjoy protection in accordance with them, not, however, as citizens but as cobeneficiaries
of this protection. [Schutzgenossen] All right, that is to
say, depends upon laws. But a public law that determines for everyone what is
to be rightfully permitted or forbidden him is the act of a public will, from which all right proceeds and which
must therefore itself be incapable of doing wrong to anyone. But this is
possible through no other will than that of the entire people (since all decide
about all, hence each about himself); for it is only to oneself that one can
never do wrong. But if it is another, then the mere will of one distinct from
him can decide nothing about him that could not be wrong, and the law of this will
would, accordingly, require yet another law that would limit its legislation;
hence no particular will can be legislative for a commonwealth. (Strictly
speaking, the concepts of external freedom, equality, and the unity of the will
of all come together in order to
constitute this concept, and if the first two are taken together, independence
is the condition of the last where voting is required.) [zu welcher letzteren, da Stimmgebung erfordert wird ... Selbständigkeit
die Bedingung ist] This basic law, which can arise only from the general
(united) will of the people, is called the original
contract.
He who has the right to vote in
this legislation is called a citizen (citoyen, i.e., citizen of a state, not of a town, bourgeois). The quality requisite to this, apart from the natural one (of not being a child or a
woman), is only that of being one’s own master (sui iuris),
hence having some property (and any
art, craft, fine art, or science can be counted as property) that supports him,
that is, if he must acquire from others in order to live, he does so only by alienating what is his * and not by
giving others permission to make use of his powers and hence [the requisite
quality is] that, in the strict sense of the word, he serves no one other than the commonwealth. Here craftsmen and large
(or small) landowners are all equal, namely each is entided to only one vote.
For in regard to the latter without even raising the question, how it could
with right have come about that someone received as his own more land than he
could himself make use of with his own hands (for acquisition by military seizure
is not first acquisition), and how it came about that many human beings who
could otherwise have acquired a lasting status of possession were thereby
reduced merely to serving him in order to be able to live? - it would already
conflict with the above principle of equality if a law were to grant them such
a privileged rank that either their descendants should always remain large
(feudal) landowners, whose estates could not be sold or divided by inheritance
and thus be used by more of the people, or else that, if there were such a
division, no one other than those belonging to a certain class of people
decreed at will [willkürlich] could acquire
something of it. That is to say, a great landowner [Gutsbesitzer] eliminates as many smaller owners and their votes as
could take his place; thus he does not vote in their name and accordingly has
only one vote. Since it must therefore be left dependent only upon the ability,
industry, and good fortune of each member of a commonwealth for each at some
time to acquire a part of it and all to acquire the whole, but this distinction
cannot be taken into account in the universal legislation, the number of those qualified
to vote in legislation must be appraised by the number of those in the status
of possession, not by the size of their possessions.
[* Someone who makes an opus can convey it to someone else by alienating it, just as if it were his
property. But praestatio operas is not alienating something. A
domestic servant, a shop clerk, a day laborer, or even a barber are merely operarii, not artifices (in the wider sense of the word) and not members of the
state, and are thus also not qualified to be citizens. Although a man to whom I
give my firewood to chop and a tailor to whom I give my cloth to make into
clothes both seem to be in a quite similar relation to me, still the former
differs from the latter, as a barber from a wigmaker (even if I have given him
the hair for the wig) and hence as a day laborer from an artist or craftsman,
who makes a work that belongs to him until he is paid for it). The latter, in
pursuing his trade, thus exchanges his property with another (opus), the former, the use of his
powers, which he grants [bewilligt]
to another (operam). It is, I admit,
somewhat difficult to determine what is required in order to be able to claim
the rank of a human being who is his own master.]
But all who have this right to vote must agree to this law of public justice;
for otherwise there would be a dispute about rights [Rechtstreit] between those who do not agree to it and the first,
and yet another higher principle of right would be needed to decide it. Thus if
the first cannot be expected of an entire people, so that a majority of votes
and indeed not of those voting directly (in a large people) but only of those
delegated to do so as representatives of the people is all that can be foreseen
as attainable, the very principle of letting such a majority be sufficient,
adopted as with universal agreement and so by a contract, must be the ultimate
basis on which a civil constitution is established.
Conclusion
Now this is an original contract, on which alone a civil and hence thoroughly rightful
constitution among human beings can be based and a commonwealth established.
But it is by no means necessary that this contract (called contractus originarius or
pactum sociale), as a coalition of every particular and private will within
a people into a common and public will (for the sake of a merely rightful
legislation), be presupposed as a fact
(as a fact it is indeed not possible) - as
if it would first have to be proved from history that a people, into whose
rights and obligations we have entered as descendants, once actually carried
out such an act, and that it must have left some sure record or instrument of it,
orally or in writing, if one is to hold oneself bound to an already existing
civil constitution. It is instead only an
idea of reason, which, however, has its undoubted practical reality, namely
to bind every legislator to give his laws in such a way that they could have arisen from the united will
of a whole people and to regard each subject, insofar as he wants to be a
citizen, as if he has joined in voting for such a will. For this is the
touchstone of any public law’s conformity with right. In other words, if a public
law is so constituted that a whole people could
not possibly give its consent to it (as, e.g., that a certain class of subjects should have the hereditary
privilege of ruling rank), it is unjust; [nicht gerecht] but if it is only
possible that a people could agree to it, it is a duty to consider the law
just, even if the people is at present in such a situation or frame of mind
that, if consulted about it, it would probably refuse its consent. *
[* If,
e.g., a war tax were imposed proportionately on all subjects, they could not,
because they found it oppressive, say that it is unjust because in their
opinion the war may be unnecessary [Wrong.];
for they are not entitled to appraise this but instead, because it is still
always possible that the war is
unavoidable and the tax indispensable, the tax must hold in a subject’s
judgment as in conformity with right. But if, during such a war, certain
landowners were burdened with levies while others of the same rank were
exempted, it is easily seen that a whole people could not agree to a law of
this kind, and it is authorized at least to make representations against it,
since it cannot take this unequal distribution of burdens to be just.]
But this limitation obviously
holds only for the judgment of the legislator, not that of a subject. Thus if a
people now subject to a certain actual legislation were to judge that in all
probability this is detrimental to its happiness, what is to be done about it?
Should the people not resist it? The answer can only be that, on the part of
the people, there is nothing to be done about it but to obey. For what is under
discussion here is not the happiness that a subject may expect from the
institution or administration of a commonwealth but above all merely the right
that is to be secured for each by means of it, which is the supreme principle
for which all maxims having to do with a commonwealth must proceed and which is
limited by no other principle. With respect to the former (happiness) no
universally valid principle for laws can be given. For both the circumstances
of the times and the highly conflicting but always changing illusion [Wahn] in which someone places his
happiness (though no one can prescribe to him in what he should place it) make
any fixed principle impossible and [happiness] in itself unfit to be a
principle of legislation. The saying Salus
publica suprema civitatis lex est [The public well-being is the supreme law
of the state] remains undiminished in its worth and authority; but the public
well-being [Heil] that must first be taken into account is precisely
that lawful constitution which secures everyone his freedom by laws, whereby
each remains at liberty to seek his happiness in whatever way seems best to
him, provided he does not infringe upon that universal freedom in conformity
with law and hence upon the right of other fellow subjects.
If the supreme power gives laws
that are directed chiefly to happiness (the prosperity of the citizens,
increased population and the like), this is not done as the end for which a
civil constitution is established but merely as means for securing a rightful condition,
especially against a people’s external enemies. A head of state must be
authorized to judge for himself and alone whether such laws pertain to the
commonwealth’s flourishing, which is required to secure its strength and
stabiUty both internally and against external enemies, not in order, as it
were, to make the people happy against its will but only to make it exist as a
commonwealth. * Now the legislator can indeed err in his appraisal of whether
those measures are adopted prudently,
but not when he asks himself whether the law also harmonizes with the principle
of right; for there he has that idea of the original contract at hand as an
infallible standard, and indeed has it a priori (and need not, as with the
principle of happiness, wait for experience that would first have to teach him
whether his means are suitable). For, provided it is not self-contradictory
that an entire people should agree to such a law, however bitter they might
find it, the law is in conformity with right. But if a public law is in
conformity with this, and so beyond reproach (irresprehensibel) with regard to right, then there is also joined
with it authorization to coerce and, on the other’s part, a prohibition against
actively resisting the will of the legislator; that is, the power within a
state that gives effect to the law is also unopposable (irresistibel), and there exists no rightful commonwealth that can
hold its own without a force of this kind that puts down all internal
resistance, since each resistance would take place in conformity with a maxim
that, made universal, would annihilate any civil constitution and eradicate the
condition in which alone people can be in possession of rights generally.
[* Certain restrictions on
imports are included among these laws, so that the means of acquiring livelihood
will promote the subjects’ interests and not the advantage of foreigners or
encouragement of others’ industry, since a state, without the prosperity of the
people, would not possess enough strength to resist foreign enemies or to
maintain itself as a commonwealth.]
From this it follows that any
resistance to the supreme legislative power, any incitement to have the
subjects’ dissatisfaction become active, any insurrection that breaks out in
rebellion, is the highest and most punishable crime within a commonwealth,
because it destroys its foundation. And this prohibition is unconditional, so that even if that
power or its agent, the head of state, has gone so far as to violate the
original contract and has thereby, according to the subjects’ concept, forfeited
the right to be legislator inasmuch as he has empowered the government to
proceed quite violentiy (tyrannically), a subject is still not permitted any
resistance by way of counteracting force. The ground of this is that in an
already existing civil constitution the people’s judgment to determine how the constitution
should be administered is no longer valid. [das
Volk kein zu Recht beständiges Urteil mehr hat] For suppose that the people
can so judge, and indeed contrary to the judgment of the actual head of state;
who is to decide on which side the right is? Neither can make the decision as
judge in its own suit. Hence there would have to be another head above the head
of state, that would decide between him and the people; and this is
self-contradictory. Nor could a right of necessity (ius in casu necessitatis), which, as a supposed right to do wrong when in extreme (physical) need, is in any case an
absurdity,* enter here and provide a way to raise the barrier limiting the
people’s despotic power. [die Eigenmacht
des Volks] For, the head of state can as well urge that his harsh behavior
toward his subjects is justified by their recalcitrance as they can urge that
their rebellion is justified by their complaints against him of their
undeserved suffering; and who is to decide the issue? Only he who possesses the
supreme administration of public right can do so, and that is precisely the head
of state; and no one within a commonwealth can, accordingly, have a right to
contest his possession of it.
[* There is no casus necessitatis except in a case
where duties, namely an unconditional
duty and a (perhaps very important
yet) conditional duty, conflict with each other, e.g., if it is a matter of
preventing some catastrophe to the state by betraying a man who might stand in
the relationship to another of father and son. This prevention of trouble to
the former is an unconditional duty, whereas preventing misfortune to the
latter is only a conditional duty (namely, insofar as he has not made himself
guilty of a crime against the state). One of the relatives might report the
other’s plans to the authorities with the utmost reluctance, but he is
compelled by necessity (namely, moral necessity) but if it is said of someone
who, in order to preserve his own life, pushes another survivor of a shipwreck
from his plank, that he has a right to do so by his (physical) necessity, that
is quite false. For to preserve my life is only a conditional duty (if it can
be done without a crime); but not to take the life of another who is committing
no offense against me [der mich nicht
beleidigt] and does not even lead
me into the danger of losing my life is an unconditional duty. Yet teachers of
general civil right proceed quite consistently in conceding rightful
authorization for such extreme measures. [Nothülfe]
For the authorities can connect no punishment
with the prohibition, since this punishment would have to be death. But it
would be an absurd law to threaten someone with death if he did not voluntarily deliver himself up to death in
dangerous circumstances.]
Yet I find estimable men who
maintain that under certain circumstances a subject is authorized to use force
against his superiors; the only one of them I want to cite here is Achenwall, [lus Naturae. Editio Vta. Pars posterior,
§203-6.] who is very cautious, definite, and modest in his teachings on natural
right. He says: “If the danger that threatens a commonwealth as a result of
continuing to endure the injustice of the head of state is greater than the
danger to be feared from taking up arms against him, then the people can resist
him, for the sake of this right [zum
Behuf dieses Rechts] withdraw from its contract of subjection, and dethrone
him as a tyrant.” From this he concludes: “In this way the people (in relation
to its previous ruler) returns to the state of nature.”
I readily believe that neither
Achenwall nor any of the worthy men who have reasoned subtly in agreement with
him on this would ever have given their advice or assent to such a dangerous
undertaking in any case at hand; and it is hardly to be doubted that if those
uprisings by which Switzerland or the United Netherlands or even Great Britain
won its constitution, now considered so fortunate, had failed, those who read
the history of them would see in the execution of their now celebrated authors nothing
but the deserved punishment of great political criminals. For the outcome
usually mingles in our appraisal of the rightful grounds, [Rechtsgründe] though the former was uncertain and the latter
certain. But it is clear that, as far as the latter is concerned even if it is
granted that by such an uprising no wrong is done to a ruler (perhaps one who
had violated a joyeuse entrée, an actual
basic contract [zum Grunde liegenden Vertrag]
with the people nevertheless the people did wrong in the highest degree by
seeking their rights in this way; for this way of doing it (adopted as a maxim)
would make every rightful constitution insecure and introduce a condition of
complete lawlessness (status naturalis),
in which all rights cease, at least to have effect. In view of this propensity
of so many well-meaning authors to take the people’s part (to its own ruin), I
want to remark only that the cause of their doing so is in part the common
mistake, when the principle of right is under discussion, of substituting the
principle of happiness for it in their judgments, and in part that, where there
is to be found no instrument of an actual contract submitted to the
commonwealth, accepted by its head, and sanctioned by both, they take the idea
of an original contract, which is always present in reason as the basis [of a commonwealth],
as something that must actually have
taken place, and so think they can always save for the people authorization to
withdraw from the contract as it sees fit if, though by its own appraisal, the
contract has been grossly violated.*
[* Even if an actual contract
of the people with the ruler has been violated, the people cannot react at once
as a commonwealth but only as a mob.
[durch Rottierung] For the previously
existing constitution has been torn up by the people, while their organization
into a new commonwealth has not yet taken place. It is here that the condition
of anarchy arises with all the horrors that are at least possible by means of
it; and the wrong that is done here is that which each faction in the people
inflicts on the other, as is also clear from the example cited, where the
rebellious subjects ofthat state finally wanted to thrust upon one another by
force a constitution which would have been far more oppressive than the one
they abandoned: they would, namely, have been devoured by ecclesiastics and
aristocrats, instead of being able to expect greater equality in the
distribution of political burdens under one head of state ruling over all.]
Here it is obvious what evil
the principle of happiness (which is really not fit for any determinate
principle at all) gives rise to in the right of a State, just as it does in
morals, despite the best intentions of those who teach it. The sovereign wants
to make the people happy in accordance 5 with his concepts and becomes a
despot; the people are not willing to give up their universal human claim to
their own happiness and become rebels. Had it first been asked what is laid
down as right (where principles stand firm a priori and no empiricist can
bungle them), then the idea of the social contract would remain in its
incontestable authority, not however as a fact (as Danton would have it, apart
from which he declares null and void all rights and all property to be found in
the actually existing civil constitution) but only as a rational principle for
appraising any public rightful constitution. And it would then be seen that
before the general will exists the people possesses no coercive right at all
against its commander [Gebieter]
since it can rightfully use coercion only through him; but if the general will
exists, there is likewise no coerion to be exercised by it against him, since
otherwise the people itself would be the supreme commander; hence the people
never has a coercive right against the head of state (insubordination in word
or deed).
We also see this theory
adequately confirmed in practice. In the constitution of Great Britain where
the people carry on about their constitution as if it were the model for the
whole world we nevertheless find that it is quite silent about the
authorization belonging to the people in case the monarch should transgress the
contract of 1688, so that if he wanted to violate the constitution, there being
no law about such a case, the people secretly reserves to itself rebellion
against him. For, that the constitution should contain a law for such a case
authorizing the overthrow of the existing constitution, from which all
particular laws proceed (even supposing the contract violated) is an obvious
contradiction; for then it would also have to contain a publicly constituted * opposing
power, so that there would have to be a second head of state to protect the
people’s rights against the first, and then yet a third to decide between the
two, which of them had right on its side. Moreover, those leaders (or, if you
will, guardians) of the people, being concerned about such an accusation should
their undertaking fail, preferred to attribute
a voluntary abdication of government to the monarch they frightened away than
to claim the right to depose him, whereby they would have put the constitution
in obvious contradiction with itself.
[*No right within a state can
be concealed, treacherously as it were, by a secret reservation, least of all
the right that the people claims for itself as one belonging to the
constitution; for all laws of the constitution must be thought as arising out of
a public will. Thus if the constitution permitted insurrection, it would have
to declare publicly the right to it and in what way use is to be made of it.]
I will surely not be
reproached, because of these assertions, with flattering monarchs too much by
such inviolability; so, I hope, I will also be spared the reproach of
overstating the case in favor of the people when I say that the people too has
its inalienable rights against the head of state, although these cannot be
coercive rights.
Hobbes is of the opposite
opinion. According to him (de Cive, Chap.
7, §14), a head of state has no obligation to the people by the contract and
cannot do a citizen any wrong (he may make what arrangements he wants about
him). This proposition would be quite correct if a wrong were taken to mean an
injury that gives the injured party a coercive
right against the one who wronged him; but stated so generally, the
proposition is appalling.
A nonrecalcitrant subject must
be able to assume that his ruler does not want to do him any wrong.
Accordingly, since every human being still has his inalienable rights, which he
can never give up even if he wanted to and about which he is authorized to
judge for himself, while, on that assumption, the wrong that in his opinion is done
to him occurs only from the supreme power’s error or ignorance of certain
consequences of his laws, a citizen must have, with the approval of the ruler himself,
the authorization to make known publicly his opinions about what it is in the ruler’s
arrangements that seems to him to be a wrong against the commonwealth. For, to
assume that the head of state could never err or be ignorant of something would
be to represent him as favored with divine inspiration and raised above
humanity. Thus freedom of the pen kept
within the limits of esteem and love for the constitution within which one
lives by the subjects’ liberal way of thinking, which the constitution itself
instills in them (and pens themselves also keep one another within these
limits, so that they do not lose their freedom) is the sole palladium of the
people’s rights. For to want to deny them this freedom is not only tantamount
to taking from them any claim to a right with respect to the supreme commander
(according to Hobbes), but is also to withhold from the latter whose will gives
order to the subjects as citizens only by representing the general will of the
people all knowledge of matters that he himself would change if he knew about
them and to put him in contradiction with himself But to instill in a head of
state concern that unrest in the state might be aroused by [the subjects’]
thinking independently and aloud is tantamount to awakening in him mistrust of his
own power or even hatred of his people.
But the universal principle by
which a people has to appraise its rights negatively
- that is, appraise merely what may be regarded as not ordained by the supreme legislation, as with its best will is
contained in the proposition: What a
people cannot decree for itself a legislator also cannot decree for a people.
Thus if the question is, for
example: Can a law prescribing that a certain ecclesiastical constitution, once
arranged, is to continue permanentiy, be regarded as issuing from the real [eigentlichen] will of die legislator
(his intention)? then it will first be asked: May a people itself make it a law that certain articles of faith
and forms of external religion, once adopted, are to remain forever? And so: May a people hinder itself, in its
posterity, from making further progress in religious insight or from at some
time correcting old errors? It then becomes clear that an original contract of
the people that made this a law would in itself be null and void because it conflicts
with the vocation and end of humanity; hence a law given about this is not to
be regarded as the real will of the monarch, to whom counterrepresentations can
accordingly be made. In all cases, however, where something of this sort was
nevertheless arranged by the supreme legislation, general and public judgments
could be passed on it, but resistance to it in word or deed could never be
summoned.
In every commonwealth there
must be obedience under the mechanism
of the state constitution to coercive laws (applying to the whole), but there must
also be a spirit of freedom, since
each, in what has to do with universal human duties, requires to be convinced
by reason that this coercion is in conformity with right, lest he fall into
contradiction with himself. The former without the latter is the occasioning cause
[veranlassende Ursache] of all secret soceties. For it is a natural
calling of humanity to communicate with one another, especially in what
concerns people generally; hence those societies would disappear if such
freedom were favored. And how else, again, could the government get the
knowledge it requires for its own essential purpose than by letting the spirit
of freedom, so worthy of respect in its origin and in its effects, express
itself?
Nowhere does a practice that
ignores all pure rational principles deny theory so arrogantly as in the
question of what is required for a good constitution of a state. The cause is
that a lawful constitution of long standing gradually accustoms the people to a
rule of appraising its happiness as well as its rights in terms of the
condition [Zustand] in which
everything up to now has followed its quiet course, but not, conversely, to
evaluate that condition in terms of the concepts of both provided by reason;
instead [it leads the people] always to prefer that passive condition to the
dangerous situation of seeking a better one (what Hippocrates told physicians
to take to heart holds here: indicium anceps,
experimentum periculosum). [judgement
is uncertain and experiments are dangerous] Now, all constitutions of sufficientiy
long standing, whatever deficiencies they may have and for all their
differences, give the same result, namely being judgment is uncertain and
experiments are dangerous satisfied with the constitution one is in; so, if one
looks to the people’s welfare, no theory at all is really
valid, but everything rests on a practice docile to experience.
But if there is in reason
something that can be expressed by the words right of a state, and if this concept has binding force for people
opposed to one another in the antagonism of their freedom, and hence has
objective (practical) reality irrespective of the well-being or ill-being that
may arise from it (knowledge of which rests only on experience), then the right
of a state is based on a priori principles (for experience cannot teach what
right is), [was Recht sei] and there
is a theory of the right of a state,
no practice being valid unless it accords with this.
The only objection that can be
raised to this is that, although people have in their heads the idea of rights
belonging to them, they would still be unqualified and unworthy to be treated
in accord with them because of the hardness of their hearts, so that a supreme
power proceeding merely in accordance with rules of prudence may and must keep
them in order. But this desperate leap (salto
mortale) is of such a kind that, once the issue is not that oi right but
only of force, the people may also try out its own force and thus make every
lawful constitution insecure. If there is not something that through reason
compels immediate respect (such as the rights of human beings), then all
influences on the choice of human beings are incapable of restraining their [Or
perhaps “its freedom,” derselben
referring to Willkür] freedom; but
if, alongside benevolence, right speaks out loudly, human nature does not show
itself too depraved to listen deferentially to its voice. (Tum pietate gravem meritisquesi forte virum quem Conspexere, silent
arrectisque auribus adstant. Virgil.) [If they catch sight of a man
respected for his virtue and services, they are silent and stand close with
ears alert. Virgil Æneid 1.151-2.]
III. ON THE RELATION OF THEORY
TO PRACTICE IN THE RIGHT OF NATIONS CONSIDERED FROM A UNIVERSALLY PHILANTHROPIC,
THAT IS, COSMOPOLITAN POINT OF VIEW * (Against Moses Mendelssohn)
[*It is not at once obvious how
a universally philanthropic
presupposition can point the way to a cosmopolitan
constitution, and this in turn to the foundation of a right of nations as a condition in which alone the predispositions
belonging to humanity that make our species worthy of love can be developed.
But the conclusion of this part will make this connection clear.]
Is the human race as a whole to be loved,
or is it an object such that one must regard it with vexation, for which one
indeed wishes everything good (so as not to become misanthropic) but of which
one must never expect this, so that one must prefer to avert one’s eyes from
it? The reply to this question rests upon the answer one gives to
another: Are there in human nature predispositions from which one can gather
that the race will always progress toward what is better and that the evil of
present and past times will disappear in the good of future times? For in that
case we could still love the race, at least in its constant approach to the
good; otherwise, we should have to hate or despise it, whatever might be said
to the contrary by the affectations of universal philanthropy (which would then
be at most only a love of benevolence, not of delight). For, however one may
try to exact love from oneself, one cannot avoid hating what is and remains
evil, especially in deliberate mutual violation of the most sacred human rights
not exactly so as to inflict troubles upon him but still so as to have as
little as possible to do with him.
Moses Mendelssohn was of the
latter opinion (Jerusalem Section II,
pp. 44-47), which he opposed to his friend Lessing’s hypothesis of a divine education
of the human race.” It is, to him, a fantasy “that the whole, humanity here
below, should in the course of time always move forward and perfect itself.” “We
see,” he said, “the human race as a whole make small oscillations, and it never
takes a few steps forward without soon afterward sliding back twice as fast
into its former state.” (This is precisely the stone of Sisyphus; and in this
way one takes the earth, as the Indians do, as a place of atonement for ancient
sins that can now no longer be remembered.) “An individual makes progress, but
humanity constantly vacillates between fixed limits; regarded as a whole,
however, it maintains in all periods of time roughly the same level of
morality, the same measure of religion and irreligious, of virtue and vice, of
happiness (?) and misery.” He introduces these assertions by saying (p. 46): “Do
you want to guess what sort of purpose providence has for humanity? Forge no
hypotheses” (he had earlier called these “theory”); “just look around at what
is actually happening, and if you can take an overview of the history of all
past ages, look at what has happened from time immemorial. This is fact, this
must have belonged to that purpose, must have been approved within the plan of
wisdom or at least adopted along with it.”
I am of another opinion. If it is a sight
worthy of a divinity to see a virtuous man struggling with adversity and
temptations to evil and yet holding out against them, it is a sight most
unworthy, I shall not say of a divinity but even of the most common but well-disposed
human being to see the human race from period to period taking steps upward
toward virtue and soon after falling back just as deeply into vice and misery.
To watch this tragedy for a while might be moving and instructive, but the curtain
must eventually fall. For in the long run it turns into a farce; and even if
the actors do not tire of it, because they are fools, the spectator does, when
one or another act gives him sufficient grounds for gathering that the
never-ending piece is forever the same. If it is merely a play, the punishment
coming at the end can make up for his unpleasant feelings [Empfindungen] by means of the outcome. But in real life, [in der Wirklichkeit] to let countless
vices pile one upon another (even with virtues intervening), so that some day
there will be plenty to punish is, at least according to our concepts, even
contrary to the moraUty of a wise creator and ruler of the world.
I shall therefore be allowed to
assume that, since the human race is constandy advancing with respect to
culture (as its natural end) it is also to be conceived as progressing toward
what is better with respect to the moral end of its existence, and that this
will indeed be interrupted from time
to time but will never be broken off.
I do not need to prove this presupposition; it is up to its adversary to prove
[his] case. For I rest my case on my innate duty, the duty of every member oi the
series of generations to which I (as a human being in general) belong and am
yet not so good in the moral character [Beschaffenheit]
required of me as I ought to be and hence could be so to influence posterity
that it becomes always better (the possibility of this must, accordingly, also
be assumed), and to do it in such a way that this duty may be legitimately [rechtmäßig] handed down from one member
[in the series of] generations to another. It does not matter how many doubts
may be raised against my hopes from history, which, if they were proved, could
move me to desist from a task so apparently futile; as long as these doubts
cannot be made quite certain I cannot exchange the duty (as something liquidum) for the rule of prudence not
to attempt the impracticable (as something illiquidum,
since it is merely hypothetical); and however uncertain I may always be and
remain as to whether something better is to be hoped for the human race, this
cannot infringe upon the maxim, and hence upon its presupposition, necessary
for practical purposes, that it is practicable.
This hope for better times,
without which an earnest desire to do something profitable for the general
well-being [Wohl] would never have
warmed the human heart, has moreover always influenced the work of
well-disposed people; and even the good Mendelssohn must have counted on it
when he exerted himself so zealously for the enlightenment and welfare of the
nation to which he belonged. For he could not reasonably hope to bring this
about all by himself, without others after him continuing along the same path. Confronted
by the sorry sight, not so much of those troubles that oppress human beings
from natural causes as rather of those that they themselves inflict upon one
another, the mind is nevertheless cheered up by the prospect that matters could
become better in the future, and indeed with unselfish benevolence, since we
shall be long in our graves and shall not harvest the fruits we have helped to
sow. Empirical arguments [Beweisgründe]
against the success of these resolutions, which are taken on hope, accomplish
nothing here. For, that what has not succeeded up to now will therefore never
succeed does not even justify abandoning a pragmatic or technical purpose (for example,
that of flights with aerostatic balloons), still less a moral purpose that, if
only it is not demonstratively impossible to effect it, becomes a duty. Besides,
a good deal of evidence [Beweise] can
be put forward to show that in our age, as compared with all previous ages, the
human race as a whole has actually made considerable moral progress (short-term
checks can prove nothing to the contrary), and that the outcry about its
incessandy increasing depravity comes from the very fact that when it reaches a
higher level of morality it sees farther ahead, and its judgment about what one
is as compared with what one ought to be, hence our self-reproach, becomes all
the more severe the more levels of morality we have already climbed during the
whole of the course of the world that we have become acquainted with.
If we now ask by what means
this unending progress toward the better can be maintained and even
accelerated, it is soon seen that this immeasurably distant success will depend
not so much upon what we do (e.g., on
the education we give the younger generation) and by what methods we should
proceed in order to bring it about, but instead upon what human nature will do in and with us to force us onto a track we would not
readily take of our own accord. For only from nature, or rather from providence (since supreme wisdom is
required for the complete fulfillment of this end), can we expect an outcome
that is directed to the whole and from it to the parts, whereas people in their
schemes set out only from the parts and
may well remain with them, and may be able to reach the whole, as something too
great for them, in their ideas but not in their influence, especially since,
with their mutually adverse schemes, they would hardly unite for it by their
own free resolution.
Just as omnilateral violence
and the need arising from it must finally bring a people to decide to subject
itself to the coercion that reason itself prescribes to them as means, namely
to public law, and to enter into a civil
[staatsbürgerliche] constitution, so too must the need
arising from the constant wars by which states in turn try to encroach upon or
subjugate one another at last bring them, even against their will, to enter
into a cosmopolitan [weltbürgerliche] constitution; or else, if this condition [Zustand] of universal peace is still more dangerous to freedom from
another quarter, by leading to the most fearful despotism (as has indeed happened
more than once with states that have grown too large), this need must still
constrain states to enter a condition that is not a cosmopolitan commonwealth
under a single head but is still a rightful condition of federation in accordance with a commonly agreed upon right of nations.
For the advancing culture of states,
along with their growing propensity to aggrandize themselves by cunning or
violence at the expense of others, must multiply wars and give rise to higher
and higher costs because of ever larger armies (remaining under pay), kept at
the ready and in training and equipped with ever more numerous instruments of
war; meanwhile the price of all necessities constantiy rises, though a
corresponding increase in the metals representing them cannot be hoped for;
moreover, no peace lasts long enough for the savings during it to catch up with
expenditures on costs for the next war, and the invention of a national debt
against this, though certainly an ingenious expedient, is in the end a self-defeating
one; hence impotence must eventually bring about what good will ought to have
done but did not do: that each state becomes so organized internally that it is
not the head of state, whom war really costs nothing (since he wages it at
another’s cost, namely that of the people), who has the decisive voice as to
whether there is to be war or not, but instead the people, which pays for it
(admittedly, this necessarily presupposes the realization ofthat idea of the
original contract). For the people will not readily put itself in danger of personal
poverty, which does not touch the head of state, out of a mere desire for
aggrandizement or because of some supposed, merely verbal offense. And
thus posterity too (to which no burdens not incurred by it will be shifted)
could always progress to the better even in the moral sense, without love for
posterity having to be the cause of this but only the self-love of each age,
such progress being possible because every commonwealth, unable to harm another
by force, must have recourse only to right and has grounds to hope that others
similarly constituted will come to its assistance in this.
This is, however, only an
opinion and a mere hypothesis; it is uncertain, like all judgments that want to
assign for an intended effect not entirely within our control the only natural
cause adequate to it; and even as such, it does not involve a principle for the
subjects in an already existing state to enforce it (as has already been
shown), but only for uncoercible heads of state. Although in the usual order of
things it is not in the nature of the human being to relinquish his power by
choice [willkürlich] it is still not
impossible in pressing circumstances. Thus it can be considered an expression
not unbefitting the moral wishes and hopes of people (once aware of their
inability) to expect the circumstances required for these from providence, which will provide an
outcome for the end of humanity as a
whole species, to reach its final destination by the free use of its powers as
far as they extend, to which end the ends of human beings, considered
separately, are directiy opposed. For, the very opposition of inclinations to
one another, from which evil arises, furnishes reason a free play to subjugate
them all and, in place of evil, which destroys itself, to establish the rule of
good, which, once it exists, continues to maintain itself of its own accord.
Nowhere does human nature
appear less lovable than in the relations of entire peoples to one another. No state
is for a moment secure from others in either its independence or its property. The
way to subjugate one another or to diminish what belongs to another always
exists, and arming for defence, which often makes peace more oppressive and more
destructive of internal welfare than war itself, can never be relaxed. Now, the
only possible remedy for this is a right of nations, based on public laws
accompanied by power to which each state would have to submit (by analogy with
civil right, or the right of a state, among individuals); for, an enduring universal
peace by means of the so-called balance of
power in Europe is a mere fantasy, like Swift’s house that the builder had constructed
in such perfect accord with all the laws of equilibrium that it collapsed as soon
as a sparrow alighted upon it. [Stephen Walt & John Mearsheimer. Kenneth
Waltz & Hans Morgenthau & Henry Kissinger.] But, it will be said,
states will never submit to coercive laws of this kind; and a proposal for a universal
state of nations [Völkentaat] to
whose power all individual states should voluntarily accommodate themselves so
as to obey its laws however good it may sound in the theory of an Abbe St. Pierre
or of a Rousseau still does not hold in practice; and so it has always been
ridiculed by great statesmen, and still more by heads of state, as an academic and
childish idea emerging from the schools.
For my own part, I nevertheless
put my trust in theory, which proceeds from the principle of right, as to what
relations among human beings and states ought
to be, and which commends to earthly gods the maxim always so to behave in their
conflicts that such a universal state of nations will thereby be ushered in,
and so to assume that it is possible (in
praxi) and that it can be; but at the same time I put my trust (in subsidium) in the nature of things,
which constrains one to go where one does not want to go (fata volentem ducunt, nolentem
trahunt) [The fates lead the willing, drive the unwilling. Seneca Episl. mor. 18.4.] In the latter, account is also taken of human nature, in
which respect for right and duty is still alive, so that I cannot and will not take
it to be so immersed in evil that morally practical reason should not, after
many unsuccessful attempts, finally triumph over evil and present human nature as
lovable after all. Thus on the cosmopolitan level, too, it can be maintained:
What on rational grounds holds for theory also holds for practice.
No comments:
Post a Comment