The State “War is the Health of the State”
by Randolph Bourne (1918)
To most Americans of the classes which consider
themselves significant the war [World War I] brought a sense of the sanctity of
the State which, if they had had time to think about it, would have seemed a
sudden and surprising alteration in their habits of thought. In times of peace,
we usually ignore the State in favour of partisan political controversies, or
personal struggles for office, or the pursuit of party policies. It is the Government
rather than the State with which the politically minded are concerned. The
State is reduced to a shadowy emblem which comes to consciousness only on
occasions of patriotic holiday.
Government is obviously composed of common and
unsanctified men, and is thus a legitimate object of criticism and even
contempt. If your own party is in power, things may be assumed to be moving
safely enough; but if the opposition is in, then clearly all safety and honor
have fled the State. Yet you do not put it to yourself in quite that way. What
you think is only that there are rascals to be turned out of a very practical
machinery of offices and functions which you take for granted. When we say that
Americans are lawless, we usually mean that they are less conscious than other
peoples of the august majesty of the institution of the State as it stands
behind the objective government of men and laws which we see. In a republic the
men who hold office are indistinguishable from the mass. Very few of them
possess the slightest personal dignity with which they could endow their
political role; even if they ever thought of such a thing. And they have no
class distinction to give them glamour. In a republic the Government is obeyed
grumblingly, because it has no bedazzlements or sanctities to gild it. If you
are a good old-fashioned democrat, you rejoice at this fact, you glory in the
plainness of a system where every citizen has become a king. If you are more
sophisticated you bemoan the passing of dignity and honor from affairs of
State. But in practice, the democrat does not in the least treat his elected
citizen with the respect due to a king, nor does the sophisticated citizen pay
tribute to the dignity even when he finds it. The republican State has almost
no trappings to appeal to the common man’s emotions. What it has are of
military origin, and in an unmilitary era such as we have passed through since
the Civil War, even military trappings have been scarcely seen. In such an era
the sense of the State almost fades out of the consciousness of men.
With the shock of war, however, the State comes into
its own again. The Government, with no mandate from the people, without
consultation of the people, conducts all the negotiations, the backing and
filling, the menaces and explanations, which slowly bring it into collision
with some other Government, and gently and irresistibly slides the country into
war. For the benefit of proud and haughty citizens, it is fortified with a list
of the intolerable insults which have been hurled toward us by the other
nations; for the benefit of the liberal and beneficent, it has a convincing set
of moral purposes which our going to war will achieve; for the ambitious and
aggressive classes, it can gently whisper of a bigger role in the destiny of
the world. The result is that, even in those countries where the business of
declaring war is theoretically in the hands of representatives of the people,
no legislature has ever been known to decline the request of an Executive,
which has conducted all foreign affairs in utter privacy and irresponsibility,
that it order the nation into battle. Good democrats are wont to feel the
crucial difference between a State in which the popular Parliament or Congress
declares war, and the State in which an absolute monarch or ruling class
declares war. But, put to the stern pragmatic test, the difference is not
striking. In the freest of republics as well as in the most tyrannical of
empires, all foreign policy, the diplomatic negotiations which produce or
forestall war, are equally the private property of the Executive part of the
Government, and are equally exposed to no check whatever from popular bodies,
or the people voting as a mass themselves.
The moment war is declared, however, the mass of the
people, through some spiritual alchemy, become convinced that they have willed
and executed the deed themselves. They then, with the exception of a few
malcontents, proceed to allow themselves to be regimented, coerced, deranged in
all the environments of their lives, and turned into a solid manufactory of
destruction toward whatever other people may have, in the appointed scheme of
things, come within the range of the Government’s disapprobation. The citizen
throws off his contempt and indifference to Government, identifies himself with
its purposes, revives all his military memories and symbols, and the State once
more walks, an august presence, through the imaginations of men. Patriotism
becomes the dominant feeling, and produces immediately that intense and
hopeless confusion between the relations which the individual bears and should
bear toward the society of which he is a part.
The patriot loses all sense of the distinction
between State, nation, and government. In our quieter moments, the Nation or
Country forms the basic idea of society. We think vaguely of a loose population
spreading over a certain geographical portion of the earth’s surface, speaking
a common language, and living in a homogeneous civilization. Our idea of
Country concerns itself with the non-political aspects of a people, its ways of
living, its personal traits, its literature and art, its characteristic
attitudes toward life. We are Americans because we live in a certain bounded
territory, because our ancestors have carried on a great enterprise of
pioneering and colonization, because we live in certain kinds of communities
which have a certain look and express their aspirations in certain ways. We can
see that our civilization is different from contiguous civilizations like the
Indian and Mexican. The institutions of our country form a certain network
which affects us vitally and intrigues our thoughts in a way that these other
civilizations do not. We are a part of Country, for better or for worse. We
have arrived in it through the operation of physiological laws, and not in any
way through our own choice. By the time we have reached what are called years
of discretion, its influences have molded our habits, our values, our ways of
thinking, so that however aware we may become, we never really lose the stamp
of our civilization, or could be mistaken for the child of any other country.
Our feeling for our fellow countrymen is one of similarity or of mere
acquaintance. We may be intensely proud of and congenial to our particular
network of civilization, or we may detest most of its qualities and rage at its
defects. This does not alter the fact that we are inextricably bound up in it.
The Country, as an inescapable group into which we are born, and which makes us
its particular kind of a citizen of the world, seems to be a fundamental fact
of our consciousness, an irreducible minimum of social feeling.
Now this feeling for country is essentially
noncompetitive; we think of our own people merely as living on the earth’s
surface along with other groups, pleasant or objectionable as they may be, but
fundamentally as sharing the earth with them. In our simple conception of
country there is no more feeling of rivalry with other peoples than there is in
our feeling for our family. Our interest turns within rather than without, is
intensive and not belligerent. We grow up and our imaginations gradually stake
out the world we live in, they need no greater conscious satisfaction for their
gregarious impulses than this sense of a great mass of people to whom we are
more or less attuned, and in whose institutions we are functioning. The feeling
for country would be an uninflatable maximum were it not for the ideas of State
and Government which are associated with it. Country is a concept of peace, of
tolerance, of living and letting live. But State is essentially a concept of
power, of competition: it signifies a group in its aggressive aspects. And we
have the misfortune of being born not only into a country but into a State, and
as we grow up we learn to mingle the two feelings into a hopeless confusion.
The State is the country acting as a political unit,
it is the group acting as a repository of force, determiner of law, arbiter of
justice. International politics is a “power politics” because it is a relation
of States and that is what States infallibly and calamitously are, huge
aggregations of human and industrial force that may be hurled against each
other in war. When a country acts as a whole in relation to another country, or
in imposing laws on its own inhabitants, or in coercing or punishing
individuals or minorities, it is acting as a State. The history of America as a
country is quite different from that of America as a State. In one case it is
the drama of the pioneering conquest of the land, of the growth of wealth and
the ways in which it was used, of the enterprise of education, and the carrying
out of spiritual ideals, of the struggle of economic classes. But as a State,
its history is that of playing a part in the world, making war, obstructing international
trade, preventing itself from being split to pieces, punishing those citizens
whom society agrees are offensive, and collecting money to pay for all.
Government on the other hand is synonymous with
neither State nor Nation. It is the machinery by which the nation, organized as
a State, carries out its State functions. Government is a framework of the
administration of laws, and the carrying out of the public force. Government is
the idea of the State put into practical operation in the hands of definite,
concrete, fallible men. It is the visible sign of the invisible grace. It is
the word made flesh. And it has necessarily the limitations inherent in all
practicality. Government is the only form in which we can envisage the State,
but it is by no means identical with it. That the State is a mystical
conception is something that must never be forgotten. Its glamour and its
significance linger behind the framework of Government and direct its
activities.
Wartime brings the ideal of the State out into very
clear relief, and reveals attitudes and tendencies that were hidden. In times
of peace the sense of the State flags in a republic that is not militarized.
For war is essentially the health of the State. The ideal of the State is that
within its territory its power and influence should be universal. As the Church
is the medium for the spiritual salvation of man, so the State is thought of as
the medium for his political salvation. Its idealism is a rich blood flowing to
all the members of the body politic. And it is precisely in war that the
urgency for union seems greatest, and the necessity for universality seems most
unquestioned. The State is the organization of the herd to act offensively or
defensively against another herd similarly organized. The more terrifying the
occasion for defense, the closer will become the organization and the more
coercive the influence upon each member of the herd. War sends the current of
purpose and activity flowing down to the lowest level of the herd, and to its
most remote branches. All the activities of society are linked together as fast
as possible to this central purpose of making a military offensive or a
military defense, and the State becomes what in peacetimes it has vainly
struggled to become - the inexorable arbiter and determinant of men’s business
and attitudes and opinions. The slack is taken up, the cross-currents fade out,
and the nation moves lumberingly and slowly, but with ever accelerated speed
and integration, toward the great end, toward the “peacefulness of being at
war,” of which L.P. Jacks has so unforgettably spoken.
The classes which are able to play an active and not
merely a passive role in the organization for war get a tremendous liberation
of activity and energy. Individuals are jolted out of their old routine, many
of them are given new positions of responsibility, new techniques must be
learned. Wearing home ties are broken and women who would have remained
attached with infantile bonds are liberated for service overseas. A vast sense
of rejuvenescence pervades the significant classes, a sense of new importance
in the world. Old national ideals are taken out, re-adapted to the purpose and
used as universal touchstones, or molds into which all thought is poured. Every
individual citizen who in peacetimes had no function to perform by which he
could imagine himself an expression or living fragment of the State becomes an
active amateur agent of the Government in reporting spies and disloyalists, in
raising Government funds, or in propagating such measures as are considered
necessary by officialdom. Minority opinion, which in times of peace, was only
irritating and could not be dealt with by law unless it was conjoined with
actual crime, becomes, with the outbreak of war, a case for outlawry. Criticism
of the State, objections to war, lukewarm opinions concerning the necessity or
the beauty of conscription, are made subject to ferocious penalties, far
exceeding in severity those affixed to actual pragmatic crimes. Public opinion,
as expressed in the newspapers, and the pulpits and the schools, becomes one
solid block. “Loyalty,” or rather war orthodoxy, becomes the sole test for all
professions, techniques, occupations. Particularly is this true in the sphere
of the intellectual life. There the smallest taint is held to spread over the
whole soul, so that a professor of physics is ipso facto disqualified to teach
physics or to hold honorable place in a university - the republic of learning -
if he is at all unsound on the war. Even mere association with persons thus
tainted is considered to disqualify a teacher. Anything pertaining to the enemy
becomes taboo. His books are suppressed wherever possible, his language is
forbidden. His artistic products are considered to convey in the subtlest
spiritual way taints of vast poison to the soul that permits itself to enjoy
them. So enemy music is suppressed, and energetic measures of opprobrium taken
against those whose artistic consciences are not ready to perform such an act
of self-sacrifice. The rage for loyal conformity works impartially, and often
in diametric opposition to other orthodoxies and traditional conformities, or
even ideals. The triumphant orthodoxy of the State is shown at its apex perhaps
when Christian preachers lose their pulpits for taking in more or less literal
terms the Sermon on the Mount, and Christian zealots are sent to prison for
twenty years for distributing tracts which argue that war is unscriptural.
War is the health of the State. It automatically sets
in motion throughout society those irresistible forces for uniformity, for
passionate cooperation with the Government in coercing into obedience the
minority groups and individuals which lack the larger herd sense. The machinery
of government sets and enforces the drastic penalties; the minorities are
either intimidated into silence, or brought slowly around by a subtle process
of persuasion which may seem to them really to be converting them. Of course,
the ideal of perfect loyalty, perfect uniformity is never really attained. The
classes upon whom the amateur work of coercion falls are unwearied in their
zeal, but often their agitation instead of converting, merely serves to stiffen
their resistance. Minorities are rendered sullen, and some intellectual opinion
bitter and satirical. But in general, the nation in wartime attains a
uniformity of feeling, a hierarchy of values culminating at the undisputed apex
of the State ideal, which could not possibly be produced through any other
agency than war. Loyalty - or mystic devotion to the State - becomes the major
imagined human value. Other values, such as artistic creation, knowledge,
reason, beauty, the enhancement of life, are instantly and almost unanimously
sacrificed, and the significant classes who have constituted themselves the
amateur agents of the State are engaged not only in sacrificing these values
for themselves but in coercing all other persons into sacrificing them.
War - or at least modern war waged by a democratic
republic against a powerful enemy - seems to achieve for a nation almost all
that the most inflamed political idealist could desire. Citizens are no longer
indifferent to their Government, but each cell of the body politic is brimming
with life and activity. We are at last on the way to full realization of that
collective community in which each individual somehow contains the virtue of
the whole. In a nation at war, every citizen identifies himself with the whole,
and feels immensely strengthened in that identification. The purpose and desire
of the collective community live in each person who throws himself
wholeheartedly into the cause of war. The impeding distinction between society
and the individual is almost blotted out. At war, the individual becomes almost
identical with his society. He achieves a superb self-assurance, an intuition
of the rightness of all his ideas and emotions, so that in the suppression of
opponents or heretics he is invincibly strong; he feels behind him all the
power of the collective community. The individual as social being in war seems
to have achieved almost his apotheosis. Not for any religious impulse could the
American nation have been expected to show such devotion en masse, such
sacrifice and labor. Certainly not for any secular good, such as universal
education or the subjugation of nature, would it have poured forth its treasure
and its life, or would it have permitted such stern coercive measures to be
taken against it, such as conscripting its money and its men. But for the sake
of a war of offensive self-defense, undertaken to support a difficult cause to
the slogan of “democracy,” it would reach the highest level ever known of
collective effort.
For these secular goods, connected with the
enhancement of life, the education of man and the use of the intelligence to
realize reason and beauty in the nation’s communal living, are alien to our
traditional ideal of the State. The State is intimately connected with war, for
it is the organization of the collective community when it acts in a political
manner, and to act in a political manner towards a rival group has meant,
throughout all history - war.
There is nothing invidious in the use of the term “herd”
in connection with the State. It is merely an attempt to reduce closer to first
principles the nature of this institution in the shadow of which we all live,
move, and have our being. Ethnologists are generally agreed that human society
made its first appearance as the human pack and not as a collection of
individuals or of couples. The herd is in fact the original unit, and only as
it was differentiated did personal individuality develop. All the most
primitive surviving tribes of men are shown to live in a very complex but very
rigid social organization where opportunity for individuation is scarcely
given. These tribes remain strictly organized herds, and the difference between
them and the modern State is one of degree of sophistication and variety of
organization, and not of kind.
Psychologists recognize the gregarious impulse as one
of the strongest primitive pulls which keeps together the herds of the
different species of higher animals. Mankind is no exception. Our pugnacious
evolutionary history has prevented the impulse from ever dying out. This
gregarious impulse is the tendency to imitate, to conform, to coalesce together,
and is most powerful when the herd believes itself threatened with attack.
Animals crowd together for protection, and men become most conscious of their
collectivity at the threat of war.
Consciousness of collectivity brings confidence and a
feeling of massed strength, which in turn arouses pugnacity and the battle is
on. In civilized man, the gregarious impulse acts not only to produce concerted
action for defense, but also to produce identity of opinion. Since thought is a
form of behavior, the gregarious impulse floods up into its realms and demands
that sense of uniform thought which wartime produces so successfully. And it is
in this flooding of the conscious life of society that gregariousness works its
havoc.
For just as in modern societies the sex instinct is
enormously oversupplied for the requirements of human propagation, so the
gregarious impulse is enormously oversupplied for the work of protection which
it is called upon to perform. It would be quite enough if we were gregarious
enough to enjoy the companionship of others, to be able to cooperate with them,
and to feel a slight malaise at solitude. Unfortunately, however, this impulse
is not content with these reasonable and healthful demands, but insists that
like-mindedness shall prevail everywhere, in all departments of life. So that
all human progress, all novelty, and nonconformity, must be carried against the
resistance of this tyrannical herd instinct which drives the individual into
obedience and conformity with the majority. Even in the most modern and
enlightened societies this impulse shows little sign of abating. As it is
driven by inexorable economic demand out of the sphere of utility, it seems to
fasten itself ever more fiercely in the realm of feeling and opinion, so that conformity
comes to be a thing aggressively desired and demanded.
The gregarious impulse keeps its hold all the more
virulently because when the group is in motion or is taking any positive
action, this feeling of being with and supported by the collective herd very
greatly feeds that will to power, the nourishment of which the individual
organism so constantly demands. You feel powerful by conforming, and you feel
forlorn and helpless if you are out of the crowd. While even if you do not get
any access of power by thinking and feeling just as everybody else in your
group does, you get at least the warm feeling of obedience, the soothing
irresponsibility of protection.
Joining as it does to these very vigorous tendencies
of the individual - the pleasure in power and the pleasure in obedience - this
gregarious impulse becomes irresistible in society. War stimulates it to the
highest possible degree, sending the influences of its mysterious herd-current
with its inflations of power and obedience to the farthest reaches of the
society, to every individual and little group that can possibly be affected.
And it is these impulses which the State - the organization of the entire herd,
the entire collectivity - is founded on and makes use of.
There is, of course, in the feeling toward the State
a large element of pure filial mysticism. The sense of insecurity, the desire
for protection, sends one’s desire back to the father and mother, with whom is
associated the earliest feelings of protection. It is not for nothing that one’s
State is still thought of as Father or Motherland, that one’s relation toward
it is conceived in terms of family affection. The war has shown that nowhere
under the shock of danger have these primitive childlike attitudes failed to
assert themselves again, as much in this country as anywhere. If we have not
the intense Father-sense of the German who worships his Vaterland, at least in
Uncle Sam we have a symbol of protecting, kindly authority, and in the many
Mother-posters of the Red Cross, we see how easily in the more tender functions
of war service, the ruling organization is conceived in family terms. A people
at war have become in the most literal sense obedient, respectful, trustful
children again, full of that naïve faith in the all-wisdom and all-power of the
adult who takes care of them, imposes his mild but necessary rule upon them and
in whom they lose their responsibility and anxieties. In this recrudescence of
the child, there is great comfort, and a certain influx of power. On most people
the strain of being an independent adult weighs heavily, and upon none more
than those members of the significant classes who have had bequeathed to them
or have assumed the responsibilities of governing. The State provides the
convenientest of symbols under which these classes can retain all the actual
pragmatic satisfaction of governing, but can rid themselves of the psychic
burden of adulthood. They continue to direct industry and government and all
the institutions of society pretty much as before, but in their own conscious
eyes and in the eyes of the general public, they are turned from their selfish
and predatory ways, and have become loyal servants of society, or something
greater than they - the State. The man who moves from the direction of a large
business in New York to a post in the war management industrial service in
Washington does not apparently alter very much his power or his administrative
technique. But psychically, what a transfiguration has occurred! His is now not
only the power but the glory! And his sense of satisfaction is directly
proportional not to the genuine amount of personal sacrifice that may be
involved in the change but to the extent to which he retains his industrial
prerogatives and sense of command.
From members of this class a certain insuperable
indignation arises if the change from private enterprise to State service
involves any real loss of power and personal privilege. If there is to be
pragmatic sacrifice, let it be, they feel, on the field of honor, in the traditionally
acclaimed deaths by battle, in that detour to suicide, as Nietzsche calls war.
The State in wartime supplies satisfaction for this very real craving, but its
chief value is the opportunity it gives for this regression to infantile
attitudes. In your reaction to an imagined attack on your country or an insult
to its government, you draw closer to the herd for protection, you conform in
word and deed, and you insist vehemently that everybody else shall think,
speak, and act together. And you fix your adoring gaze upon the State, with a
truly filial look, as upon the Father of the flock, the quasi-personal symbol
of the strength of the herd, and the leader and determinant of your definite
action and ideas.
The members of the working classes, that portion at
least which does not identify itself with the significant classes and seek to
imitate it and rise to it, are notoriously less affected by the symbolism of
the State, or, in other words, are less patriotic than the significant classes.
For theirs is neither the power nor the glory. The State in wartime does not
offer them the opportunity to regress, for, never having acquired social
adulthood, they cannot lose it. If they have been drilled and regimented, as by
the industrial regime of the last century, they go out docilely enough to do
battle for their State, but they are almost entirely without that filial sense
and even without that herd-intellect sense which operates so powerfully among
their “betters.” They live habitually in an industrial serfdom, by which,
though nominally free, they are in practice as a class bound to a system of
machine-production the implements of which they do not own, and in the
distribution of whose product they have not the slightest voice, except what
they can occasionally exert by a veiled intimidation which draws slightly more
of the product in their direction. From such serfdom, military conscription is
not so great a change. But into the military enterprise they go, not with those
hurrahs of the significant classes whose instincts war so powerfully feeds, but
with the same apathy with which they enter and continue in the industrial
enterprise.
From this point of view, war can be called almost an
upper-class sport. The novel interests and excitements it provides, the inflations
of power, the satisfaction it gives to those very tenacious human impulses -
gregariousness and parent-regression - endow it with all the qualities of a
luxurious collective game which is felt intensely just in proportion to the
sense of significant rule the person has in the class division of his society.
A country at war - particularly our own country at war - does not act as a
purely homogeneous herd. The significant classes have all the herd-feeling in
all its primitive intensity, but there are barriers, or at least differentials
of intensity, so that this feeling does not flow freely without impediment
throughout the entire nation. A modern country represents a long historical and
social process of disaggregation of the herd. The nation at peace is not a
group, it is a network of myriads of groups representing the cooperation and
similar feeling of men on all sorts of planes and in all sorts of human
interests and enterprises. In every modern industrial country, there are
parallel planes of economic classes with divergent attitudes and institutions
and interests - bourgeois and proletariat, with their many subdivisions
according to power and function, and even their interweaving, such as those
more highly skilled workers who habitually identify themselves with the owning
and the significant classes and strive to raise themselves to the bourgeois
level, imitating their cultural standards and manners. Then there are religious
groups with a certain definite, though weakening sense of kinship, and there
are the powerful ethnic groups which behave almost as cultural colonies in the
New World, clinging tenaciously to language and historical tradition, though
their herdishness is usually founded on cultural rather than State symbols.
There are even certain vague sectional groupings. All these small sects,
political parties, classes, levels, interests, may act as foci for
herd-feelings. They intersect and interweave, and the same person may be a
member of several different groups lying at different planes. Different
occasions will set off his herd-feeling in one direction or another. In a
religious crisis he will be intensely conscious of the necessity that his sect
(or sub-herd) may prevail, in a political campaign, that his party shall
triumph.
To the spread of herd-feeling, therefore, all these
smaller herds offer resistance. To the spread of that herd-feeling which arises
from the threat of war, and which would normally involve the entire nation, the
only groups which make serious resistance are those, of course, which continue
to identify themselves with the other nation from which they or their parents
have come. In times of peace they are for all practical purposes citizens of
their new country. They keep alive their ethnic traditions more as a luxury than
anything. Indeed these traditions tend rapidly to die out except where they
connect with some still unresolved nationalistic cause abroad, with some
struggle for freedom, or some irredentism. If they are consciously opposed by a
too invidious policy of Americanism, they tend to be strengthened. And in time
of war, these ethnic elements which have any traditional connection with the
enemy, even though most of the individuals may have little real sympathy with
the enemy’s cause, are naturally lukewarm to the herd-feeling of the nation
which goes back to State traditions in which they have no share. But to the
natives imbued with State-feeling, any such resistance or apathy is
intolerable. This herd-feeling, this newly awakened consciousness of the State,
demands universality. The leaders of the significant classes, who feel most
intensely this State compulsion, demand a 100 percent Americanism, among 100
percent of the population. The State is a jealous God and will brook no rivals.
Its sovereignty must pervade every one, and all feeling must be run into the
stereotyped forms of romantic patriotic militarism which is the traditional
expression of the State herd-feeling.
Thus arises conflict within the State. War becomes
almost a sport between the hunters and the hunted. The pursuit of enemies
within outweighs in psychic attractiveness the assault on the enemy without.
The whole terrific force of the State is brought to bear against the heretics.
The nation boils with a slow insistent fever. A white terrorism is carried on
by the Government against pacifists, socialists, enemy aliens, and a milder
unofficial persecution against all persons or movements that can be imagined as
connected with the enemy. War, which should be the health of the State, unifies
all the bourgeois elements and the common people, and outlaws the rest. The
revolutionary proletariat shows more resistance to this unification, is, as we
have seen, psychically out of the current. Its vanguard, as the I.W.W., is
remorselessly pursued, in spite of the proof that it is a symptom, not a cause,
and its persecution increases the disaffection of labor and intensifies the
friction instead of lessening it.
But the emotions that play around the defense of the
State do not take into consideration the pragmatic results. A nation at war,
led by its significant classes, is engaged in liberating certain of its
impulses which have had all too little exercise in the past. It is getting
certain satisfactions, and the actual conduct of the war or the condition of
the country are really incidental to the enjoyment of new forms of virtue and
power and aggressiveness. If it could be shown conclusively that the
persecution of slightly disaffected elements actually increased enormously the
difficulties of production and the organization of the war technique, it would
be found that public policy would scarcely change. The significant classes must
have their pleasure in hunting down and chastising everything that they feel
instinctively to be not imbued with the current State enthusiasm, though the
State itself be actually impeded in its efforts to carry out those objects for
which they are passionately contending. The best proof of this is that with a
pursuit of plotters that has continued with ceaseless vigilance ever since the
beginning of the war in Europe, the concrete crimes unearthed and punished have
been fewer than those prosecutions for the mere crime of opinion or the
expression of sentiments critical of the State or the national policy. The
punishment for opinion has been far more ferocious and unintermittent than the
punishment of pragmatic crime. Unimpeachable Anglo-Saxon Americans who were
freer of pacifist or socialist utterance than the State-obsessed ruling public
opinion, received heavier penalties and even greater opprobrium, in many
instances, than the definitely hostile German plotter. A public opinion which,
almost without protest, accepts as just, adequate, beautiful, deserved, and in
fitting harmony with ideals of liberty and freedom of speech, a sentence of
twenty years in prison for mere utterances, no matter what they may be, shows
itself to be suffering from a kind of social derangement of values, a sort of
social neurosis, that deserves analysis and comprehension.
On our entrance into the war, there were many persons
who predicted exactly this derangement of values, who feared lest democracy
suffer more at home from an America at war than could be gained for democracy
abroad. That fear has been amply justified. The question whether the American nation
would act like an enlightened democracy going to war for the sake of high
ideals, or like a State-obsessed herd, has been decisively answered. The record
is written and cannot be erased. History will decide whether the terrorization
of opinion and the regimentation of life were justified under the most
idealistic of democratic administrations. It will see that when the American
nation had ostensibly a chance to conduct a gallant war, with scrupulous regard
to the safety of democratic values at home, it chose rather to adopt all the
most obnoxious and coercive techniques of the enemy and of the other countries
at war, and to rival in intimidation and ferocity of punishment the worst
governmental systems of the age. For its former unconsciousness and disrespect
of the State ideal, the nation apparently paid the penalty in a violent swing
to the other extreme. It acted so exactly like a herd in its irrational
coercion of minorities that there is no artificiality in interpreting the
progress of the war in terms of the herd psychology. It unwittingly brought out
into the strongest relief the true characteristics of the State and its
intimate alliance with war. It provided for the enemies of war and the critics
of the State the most telling arguments possible. The new passion for the State
ideal unwittingly set in motion and encouraged forces that threaten very
materially to reform the State. It has shown those who are really determined to
end war that the problem is not the mere simple one of finishing a war that
will end war.
For war is a complicated way in which a nation acts,
and it acts so out of a spiritual compulsion which pushes it on, perhaps
against all its interests, all its real desires, and all its real sense of
values. It is States that make wars and not nations, and the very thought and
almost necessity of war is bound up with the ideal of the State. Not for
centuries have nations made war; in fact the only historical example of nations
making war is the great barbarian invasions into southern Europe, the invasions
of Russia from the East, and perhaps the sweep of Islam through northern Africa
into Europe after Mohammed’s death. And the motivations for such wars were
either the restless expansion of migratory tribes or the flame of religious
fanaticism. Perhaps these great movements could scarcely be called wars at all,
for war implies an organized people drilled and led: in fact, it necessitates
the State. Ever since Europe has had any such organization, such huge conflicts
between nations - nations, that is, as cultural groups - have been unthinkable.
It is preposterous to assume that for centuries in Europe there would have been
any possibility of a people en masse (with their own leaders, and not with the
leaders of their duly constituted State) rising up and overflowing their
borders in a war raid upon a neighboring people. The wars of the Revolutionary
armies of France were clearly in defense of an imperiled freedom, and,
moreover, they were clearly directed not against other peoples, but against the
autocratic governments that were combining to crush the Revolution. There is no
instance in history of a genuinely national war. There are instances of
national defenses, among primitive civilizations such as the Balkan peoples,
against intolerable invasion by neighboring despots or oppression. But war, as
such, cannot occur except in a system of competing States, which have relations
with each other through the channels of diplomacy.
War is a function of this system of States, and could
not occur except in such a system. Nations organized for internal
administration, nations organized as a federation of free communities, nations
organized in any way except that of a political centralization of a dynasty, or
the reformed descendant of a dynasty, could not possibly make war upon each
other. They would not only have no motive for conflict, but they would be
unable to muster the concentrated force to make war effective. There might be
all sorts of amateur marauding, there might be guerrilla expeditions of group
against group, but there could not be that terrible war en masse of the
national State, that exploitation of the nation in the interests of the State,
that abuse of the national life and resource in the frenzied mutual suicide,
which is modern war.
It cannot be too firmly realized that war is a
function of States and not of nations, indeed that it is the chief function of
States. War is a very artificial thing. It is not the naïve spontaneous
outburst of herd pugnacity; it is no more primary than is formal religion. War
cannot exist without a military establishment, and a military establishment
cannot exist without a State organization. War has an immemorial tradition and
heredity only because the State has a long tradition and heredity. But they are
inseparably and functionally joined. We cannot crusade against war without
crusading implicitly against the State. And we cannot expect, or take measures
to ensure, that this war is a war to end war, unless at the same time we take
measures to end the State in its traditional form. The State is not the nation,
and the State can be modified and even abolished in its present form, without
harming the nation. On the contrary, with the passing of the dominance of the
State, the genuine life-enhancing forces of the nation will be liberated. If
the State’s chief function is war, then the State must suck out of the nation a
large part of its energy for its purely sterile purposes of defense and
aggression. It devotes to waste or to actual destruction as much as it can of
the vitality of the nation. No one will deny that war is a vast complex of
life-destroying and life-crippling forces. If the State’s chief function is
war, then it is chiefly concerned with coordinating and developing the powers
and techniques which make for destruction. And this means not only the actual
and potential destruction of the enemy, but of the nation at home as well. For
the very existence of a State in a system of States means that the nation lies
always under a risk of war and invasion, and the calling away of energy into
military pursuits means a crippling of the productive and life-enhancing
processes of the national life.
All this organization of death-dealing energy and
technique is not a natural but a very sophisticated process. Particularly in
modern nations, but also all through the course of modern European history, it
could never exist without the State. For it meets the demands of no other
institution, it follows the desires of no religious, industrial, political
group. If the demand for military organization and a military establishment
seems to come not from the officers of the State but from the public, it is
only that it comes from the State-obsessed portion of the public, those groups
which feel most keenly the State ideal. And in this country we have had
evidence all too indubitable how powerless the pacifically minded officers of
State may be in the face of a State obsession of the significant classes. If a
powerful section of the significant classes feels more intensely the attitudes
of the State, then they will most infallibly mold the Government in time to
their wishes, bring it back to act as the embodiment of the State which it
pretends to be. In every country we have seen groups that were more loyal than
the king - more patriotic than the Government - the Ulsterites in Great
Britain, the Junkers in Prussia, l’Action Française in France, our patrioteers
in America. These groups exist to keep the steering wheel of the State
straight, and they prevent the nation from ever veering very far from the State
ideal.
Militarism expresses the desires and satisfies the
major impulse only of this class. The other classes, left to themselves, have
too many necessities and interests and ambitions, to concern themselves with so
expensive and destructive a game. But the State-obsessed group is either able
to get control of the machinery of the State or to intimidate those in control,
so that it is able through use of the collective force to regiment the other
grudging and reluctant classes into a military program. State idealism
percolates down through the strata of society; capturing groups and individuals
just in proportion to the prestige of this dominant class. So that we have the
herd actually strung along between two extremes, the militaristic patriots at
one end, who are scarcely distinguishable in attitude and animus from the most
reactionary Bourbons of an Empire, and unskilled labor groups, which entirely
lack the State sense. But the State acts as a whole, and the class that controls
governmental machinery can swing the effective action of the herd as a whole.
The herd is not actually a whole, emotionally. But by an ingenious mixture of
cajolery, agitation, intimidation, the herd is licked into shape, into an
effective mechanical unity, if not into a spiritual whole. Men are told
simultaneously that they will enter the military establishment of their own
volition, as their splendid sacrifice for their country’s welfare, and that if
they do not enter they will be hunted down and punished with the most horrid
penalties; and under a most indescribable confusion of democratic pride and
personal fear they submit to the destruction of their livelihood if not their
lives, in a way that would formerly have seemed to them so obnoxious as to be
incredible.
In this great herd machinery, dissent is like sand in
the bearings. The State ideal is primarily a sort of blind animal push toward
military unity. Any difference with that unity turns the whole vast impulse
toward crushing it. Dissent is speedily outlawed, and the Government, backed by
the significant classes and those who in every locality, however small,
identify themselves with them, proceeds against the outlaws, regardless of
their value to the other institutions of the nation, or to the effect their
persecution may have on public opinion. The herd becomes divided into the
hunters and the hunted, and war enterprise becomes not only a technical game
but a sport as well.
It must never be forgotten that nations do not
declare war on each other, nor in the strictest sense is it nations that fight
each other. Much has been said to the effect that modern wars are wars of whole
peoples and not of dynasties. Because the entire nation is regimented and the
whole resources of the country are levied on for war, this does not mean that
it is the country qua country which is fighting. It is the country organized as
a State that is fighting, and only as a State would it possibly fight. So
literally it is States which make war on each other and not peoples.
Governments are the agents of States, and it is Governments which declare war
on each other, acting truest to form in the interests of the great State ideal
they represent. There is no case known in modern times of the people being
consulted in the initiation of a war. The present demand for “democratic
control” of foreign policy indicates how completely, even in the most
democratic of modern nations, foreign policy has been the secret private
possession of the executive branch of the Government.
However representative of the people Parliaments and
Congresses may be in all that concerns the internal administration of a country’s
political affairs, in international relations it has never been possible to
maintain that the popular body acted except as a wholly mechanical ratifier of
the Executive’s will. The formality by which Parliaments and Congresses declare
war is the merest technicality. Before such a declaration can take place, the
country will have been brought to the very brink of war by the foreign policy
of the Executive. A long series of steps on the downward path, each one more
fatally committing the unsuspecting country to a warlike course of action, will
have been taken without either the people or its representatives being
consulted or expressing its feeling. When the declaration of war is finally
demanded by the Executive, the Parliament or Congress could not refuse it
without reversing the course of history, without repudiating what has been
representing itself in the eyes of the other States as the symbol and
interpreter of the nation’s will and animus. To repudiate an Executive at that
time would be to publish to the entire world the evidence that the country had
been grossly deceived by its own Government, that the country with an almost
criminal carelessness had allowed its Government to commit it to gigantic
national enterprises in which it had no heart. In such a crisis, even a
Parliament which in the most democratic States represents the common man and
not the significant classes who most strongly cherish the State ideal, will
cheerfully sustain the foreign policy which it understands even less than it
would care for if it understood, and will vote almost unanimously for an
incalculable war, in which the nation may be brought well nigh to ruin. That is
why the referendum which was advocated by some people as a test of American
sentiment in entering the war was considered even by thoughtful democrats to be
something subtly improper. The die had been cast. Popular whim could only
derange and bungle monstrously the majestic march of State policy in its new
crusade for the peace of the world. The irresistible State ideal got hold of
the bowels of men. Whereas up to this time, it had been irreproachable to be
neutral in word and deed, for the foreign policy of the State had so decided
it, henceforth it became the most arrant crime to remain neutral. The Middle
West, which had been soddenly pacifistic in our days of neutrality, became in a
few months just as soddenly bellicose, and in its zeal for witch-burnings and
its scent for enemies within gave precedence to no section of the country. The
herd-mind followed faithfully the State-mind and, the agitation for a
referendum being soon forgotten, the country fell into the universal conclusion
that, since its Congress had formally declared the war, the nation itself had
in the most solemn and universal way devised and brought on the entire affair.
Oppression of minorities became justified on the plea
that the latter were perversely resisting the rationally constructed and
solemnly declared will of a majority of the nation. The herd coalescence of
opinion which became inevitable the moment the State had set flowing the war
attitudes became interpreted as a prewar popular decision, and disinclination
to bow to the herd was treated as a monstrously antisocial act. So that the
State, which had vigorously resisted the idea of a referendum and clung
tenaciously and, of course, with entire success to its autocratic and absolute
control of foreign policy, had the pleasure of seeing the country, within a few
months, given over to the retrospective impression that a genuine referendum
had taken place. When once a country has lapped up these State attitudes, its
memory fades; it conceives itself not as merely accepting, but of having itself
willed, the whole policy and technique of war. The significant classes, with
their trailing satellites, identify themselves with the State, so that what the
State, through the agency of the Government, has willed, this majority conceives
itself to have willed.
All of which goes to show that the State represents
all the autocratic, arbitrary, coercive, belligerent forces within a social
group, it is a sort of complexus of everything most distasteful to the modern
free creative spirit, the feeling for life, liberty, and the pursuit of
happiness. War is the health of the State. Only when the State is at war does
the modern society function with that unity of sentiment, simple uncritical
patriotic devotion, cooperation of services, which have always been the ideal
of the State lover. With the ravages of democratic ideas, however, the modern
republic cannot go to war under the old conceptions of autocracy and
death-dealing belligerency. If a successful animus for war requires a
renaissance of State ideals, they can only come back under democratic forms,
under this retrospective conviction of democratic control of foreign policy,
democratic desire for war, and particularly of this identification of the
democracy with the State. How unregenerate the ancient State may be, however,
is indicated by the laws against sedition, and by the Government’s unreformed
attitude on foreign policy. One of the first demands of the more farseeing
democrats in the democracies of the Alliance was that secret diplomacy must go.
The war was seen to have been made possible by a web of secret agreements
between States, alliances that were made by Governments without the shadow of
popular support or even popular knowledge, and vague, half-understood
commitments that scarcely reached the stage of a treaty or agreement, but which
proved binding in the event. Certainly, said these democratic thinkers, war can
scarcely be avoided unless this poisonous underground system of secret
diplomacy is destroyed, this system by which a nation’s power, wealth, and
manhood may be signed away like a blank check to an allied nation to be cashed
in at some future crisis. Agreements which are to affect the lives of whole
peoples must be made between peoples and not by Governments, or at least by
their representatives in the full glare of publicity and criticism.
Such a demand for “democratic control of foreign
policy” seemed axiomatic. Even if the country had been swung into war by steps
taken secretly and announced to the public only after they had been
consummated, it was felt that the attitude of the American State toward foreign
policy was only a relic of the bad old days and must be superseded in the new
order. The American President himself, the liberal hope of the world, had
demanded, in the eyes of the world, open diplomacy, agreements freely and
openly arrived at. Did this mean a genuine transference of power in this most
crucial of State functions from Government to people? Not at all. When the
question recently came to a challenge in Congress, and the implications of open
discussion were somewhat specifically discussed, and the desirabilities frankly
commended, the President let his disapproval be known in no uncertain way. No
one ever accused Mr. Wilson of not being a State idealist, and whenever
democratic aspirations swung ideals too far out of the State orbit, he could be
counted on to react vigorously. Here was a clear case of conflict between
democratic idealism and the very crux of the concept of the State. However
unthinkingly he might have been led on to encourage open diplomacy in his
liberalizing program, when its implication was made vivid to him, he betrayed
how mere a tool the idea had been in his mind to accentuate America’s redeeming
role. Not in any sense as a serious pragmatic technique had he thought of a
genuinely open diplomacy. And how could he? For the last stronghold of State
power is foreign policy. It is in foreign policy that the State acts most
concentratedly as the organized herd, acts with fullest sense of aggressive-power,
acts with freest arbitrariness. In foreign policy, the State is most itself.
States, with reference to each other, may be said to be in a continual state of
latent war. The “armed truce,” a phrase so familiar before 1914, was an
accurate description of the normal relation of States when they are not at war.
Indeed, it is not too much to say that the normal relation of States is war.
Diplomacy is a disguised war, in which States seek to gain by barter and
intrigue, by the cleverness of wits, the objectives which they would have to
gain more clumsily by means of war. Diplomacy is used while the States are
recuperating from conflicts in which they have exhausted themselves. It is the
wheedling and the bargaining of the worn-out bullies as they rise from the
ground and slowly restore their strength to begin fighting again. If diplomacy
had been a moral equivalent for war, a higher stage in human progress, an
inestimable means of making words prevail instead of blows, militarism would
have broken down and given place to it. But since it is a mere temporary
substitute, a mere appearance of war’s energy under another form, a surrogate
effect is almost exactly proportioned to the armed force behind it. When it
fails, the recourse is immediate to the military technique whose thinly veiled
arm it has been. A diplomacy that was the agency of popular democratic forces
in their non-State manifestations would be no diplomacy at all. It would be no
better than the Railway or Education commissions that are sent from one country
to another with rational constructive purpose. The State, acting as a
diplomatic-military ideal, is eternally at war. Just as it must act arbitrarily
and autocratically in time of war, it must act in time of peace in this
particular role where it acts as a unit. Unified control is necessarily
autocratic control.
Democratic control of foreign policy is therefore a
contradiction in terms. Open discussion destroys swiftness and certainty of
action. The giant State is paralyzed. Mr. Wilson retains his full ideal of the
State at the same time that he desires to eliminate war. He wishes to make the
world safe for democracy as well as safe for diplomacy. When the two are in
conflict, his clear political insight, his idealism of the State, tells him
that it is the naïver democratic values that must be sacrificed. The world must
primarily be made safe for diplomacy. The State must not be diminished.
What is the State essentially? The more closely we
examine it, the more mystical and personal it becomes. On the Nation we can put
our hand as a definite social group, with attitudes and qualities exact enough
to mean something. On the Government we can put our hand as a certain
organization of ruling functions, the machinery of lawmaking and law-enforcing.
The Administration is a recognizable group of political functionaries,
temporarily in charge of the government. But the State stands as an idea behind
them all, eternal, sanctified, and from it Government and Administration
conceive themselves to have the breath of life. Even the nation, especially in
times of war - or at least, its significant classes - considers that it derives
its authority and its purpose from the idea of the State. Nation and State are
scarcely differentiated, and the concrete, practical, apparent facts are sunk
in the symbol. We reverence not our country but the flag. We may criticize ever
so severely our country, but we are disrespectful to the flag at our peril. It
is the flag and the uniform that make men’s heart beat high and fill them with
noble emotions, not the thought of and pious hopes for America as a free and
enlightened nation.
It cannot be said that the object of emotion is the
same, because the flag is the symbol of the nation, so that in reverencing the
American flag we are reverencing the nation. For the flag is not a symbol of
the country as a cultural group, following certain ideals of life, but solely a
symbol of the political State, inseparable from its prestige and expansion. The
flag is most intimately connected with military achievement, military memory.
It represents the country not in its intensive life, but in its far-flung
challenge to the world. The flag is primarily the banner of war; it is allied
with patriotic anthem and holiday. It recalls old martial memories. A nation’s
patriotic history is solely the history of its wars, that is, of the State in
its health and glorious functioning. So in responding to the appeal of the
flag, we are responding to the appeal of the State, to the symbol of the herd
organized as an offensive and defensive body, conscious of its prowess and its
mystical herd strength.
Even those authorities in the present Administration,
to whom has been granted autocratic control over opinion, feel, though they are
scarcely able to philosophize over, this distinction. It has been
authoritatively declared that the horrid penalties against seditious opinion
must not be construed as inhibiting legitimate, that is, partisan criticism of
the Administration. A distinction is made between the Administration and the
Government. It is quite accurately suggested by this attitude that the
Administration is a temporary band of partisan politicians in charge of the
machinery of Government, carrying out the mystical policies of State. The
manner in which they operate this machinery may be freely discussed and
objected to by their political opponents. The Governmental machinery may also
be legitimately altered, in case of necessity. What may not be discussed or
criticized is the mystical policy itself or the motives of the State in
inaugurating such a policy. The President, it is true, has made certain
partisan distinctions between candidates for office on the ground of support or
nonsupport of the Administration, but what he means was really support or nonsupport
of the State policy as faithfully carried out by the Administration. Certain of
the Administration measures were devised directly to increase the health of the
State, such as the Conscription and the Espionage laws. Others were concerned
merely with the machinery. To oppose the first was to oppose the State and was
therefore not tolerable. To oppose the second was to oppose fallible human
judgment, and was therefore, though to be depreciated, not to be wholly
interpreted as political suicide.
The distinction between Government and State,
however, has not been so carefully observed. In time of war it is natural that
Government as the seat of authority should be confused with the State or the
mystic source of authority. You cannot very well injure a mystical idea which
is the State, but you can very well interfere with the processes of Government.
So that the two become identified in the public mind, and any contempt for or
opposition to the workings of the machinery of Government is considered equivalent
to contempt for the sacred State. The State, it is felt, is being injured in
its faithful surrogate, and public emotion rallies passionately to defend it.
It even makes any criticism of the form of Government a crime.
The inextricable union of militarism and the State is
beautifully shown by those laws which emphasize interference with the Army and
Navy as the most culpable of seditious crimes. Pragmatically, a case of
capitalistic sabotage, or a strike in war industry would seem to be far more
dangerous to the successful prosecution of the war than the isolated and
ineffectual efforts of an individual to prevent recruiting. But in the
tradition of the State ideal, such industrial interference with national policy
is not identified as a crime against the State. It may be grumbled against; it
may be seen quite rationally as an impediment of the utmost gravity. But it is
not felt in those obscure seats of the herd mind which dictate the identity of
crime and fix their proportional punishments. Army and Navy, however, are the
very arms of the State; in them flows its most precious lifeblood. To paralyze
them is to touch the very State itself. And the majesty of the State is so
sacred that even to attempt such a paralysis is a crime equal to a successful
strike. The will is deemed sufficient. Even though the individual in his effort
to impede recruiting should utterly and lamentably fail, he shall be in no wise
spared. Let the wrath of the State descend upon him for his impiety! Even if he
does not try any overt action, but merely utters sentiments that may
incidentally in the most indirect way cause someone to refrain from enlisting,
he is guilty. The guardians of the State do not ask whether any pragmatic
effect flowed out of this evil will or desire. It is enough that the will is
present. Fifteen or twenty years in prison is not deemed too much for such
sacrilege.
Such attitudes and such laws, which affront every
principle of human reason, are no accident, nor are they the result of hysteria
caused by the war. They are considered just, proper, beautiful by all the
classes which have the State ideal, and they express only an extreme of health
and vigor in the reaction of the State to its nonfriends.
Such attitudes are inevitable as arising from the
devotees of the State. For the State is a personal as well as a mystical
symbol, and it can only be understood by tracing its historical origin. The
modern State is not the rational and intelligent product of modern men desiring
to live harmoniously together with security of life, property, and opinion. It
is not an organization which has been devised as pragmatic means to a desired
social end. All the idealism with which we have been instructed to endow the
State is the fruit of our retrospective imaginations. What it does for us in
the way of security and benefit of life, it does incidentally as a by-product
and development of its original functions, and not because at any time men or
classes in the full possession of their insight and intelligence have desired
that it be so. It is very important that we should occasionally lift the
incorrigible veil of that ex post facto idealism by which we throw a glamour of
rationalization over what is, and pretend in the ecstasies of social conceit
that we have personally invented and set up for the glory of God and man the
hoary institutions which we see around us. Things are what they are, and come
down to us with all their thick encrustations of error and malevolence.
Political philosophy can delight us with fantasy and convince us who need
illusion to live that the actual is a fair and approximate copy - full of
failings, of course, but approximately sound and sincere - of that ideal
society which we can imagine ourselves as creating. From this it is a step to
the tacit assumption that we have somehow had a hand in its creation and are
responsible for its maintenance and sanctity.
Nothing is more obvious, however, than that every one
of us comes into society as into something in whose creation we had not the
slightest hand. We have not even the advantage, like those little unborn souls
in The Blue Bird, of consciousness before we take up our careers on earth. By
the time we find ourselves here we are caught in a network of customs and
attitudes, the major directions of our desires and interests have been stamped
on our minds, and by the time we have emerged from tutelage and reached the
years of discretion when we might conceivably throw our influence to the
reshaping of social institutions, most of us have been so molded into the society
and class we live in that we are scarcely aware of any distinction between
ourselves as judging, desiring individuals and our social environment. We have
been kneaded so successfully that we approve of what our society approves,
desire what our society desires, and add to the group our own passionate
inertia against change, against the effort of reason, and the adventure of
beauty.
Every one of us, without exception, is born into a
society that is given, just as the fauna and flora of our environment are
given. Society and its institutions are, to the individual who enters it, as
much naturalistic phenomena as is the weather itself. There is, therefore, no
natural sanctity in the State any more than there is in the weather. We may bow
down before it, just as our ancestors bowed before the sun and moon, but it is
only because something in us unregenerate finds satisfaction in such an
attitude, not because there is anything inherently reverential in the
institution worshiped. Once the State has begun to function, and a large class
finds its interest and its expression of power in maintaining the State, this
ruling class may compel obedience from any uninterested minority. The State
thus becomes an instrument by which the power of the whole herd is wielded for
the benefit of a class. The rulers soon learn to capitalize the reverence which
the State produces in the majority, and turn it into a general resistance
toward a lessening of their privileges. The sanctity of the State becomes
identified with the sanctity of the ruling class, and the latter are permitted
to remain in power under the impression that in obeying and serving them, we
are obeying and serving society, the nation, the great collectivity of all of
us....
No comments:
Post a Comment