CHAPTER XIII. EVIDENCE.
“In consequence of some very wonderful laws, which
regulate the successions of our mental phenomena, the science of mind is, in
all its most important respects, a science of analysis.” Brown’s Lect., i., 108.
BEFORE leaving the subject of Belief, it will be
proper to shew, in a few words, what is included, under the name Evidence.
Evidence, is either the same thing with Belief, or it is the antecedent, of
which Belief is the consequent.
Belief we have seen to be of two sorts: Belief of
events; Belief of propositions.
Of events, believed on our own experience, the
evidence of the present is sense; of the past, memory; and in these cases, the
evidence and the belief are not two things, but one and the same thing. The
lamp, which at this moment lights me, I say that I see burning, and that I
believe it burning. These are two names of one and the same state of
consciousness. “I remember it was burning at the same hour last night,” and “I
believe it was burning at the same hour last night,” are also two expressions
for the same thing. In the simple anticipation of the future, from the past,
also, the evidence, and the belief, are not two things, but one and the same
thing. There is a close and inseparable association of the idea of a like
antecedent, with the idea of a like consequent. This has not a single name,
like memory; but, like memory, it is both evidence and belief.
The case of testimony is different. The Testimony is
one thing, the Belief is another. The name Evidence is given to the testimony.
The association of the testimony, with the event testified, is the belief.
Beside the belief of events which are the immediate
objects of sense, of memory, and of anticipation (the consequence of sense and
memory), and of those which are the immediate objects of testimony; there is a
belief of events which are not the immediate objects of any of those
operations. The sailor, who is shipwrecked on an unknown coast, sees the prints
of a man s foot on the sand. The print of the foot is here called the evidence;
the association of the print, as consequent, with a man, as antecedent, is
called the belief. In this case, the sensation of one event, the print of a
foot on the sand, induces the belief of another event, the existence of a man.
The sailor who has seen the mark, reports it to his companions who have not
quitted the wreck. Instantly they have the same belief; but it is a remove
farther off, and there is an additional link of evidence. The first event to
them, is the affirmation of their companion; the second, the existence of the
print; the third, that of the man. There is here evidence of evidence; the
testimony, evidence of the print; the print, evidence of the man.
The companions of the sailor, having themselves gone
on shore, perceive, indeed, no man, but see a large monkey, which leaves prints
on the sand verymuch resembling those which had first been perceived by their
companion. What is now the state of their minds? Doubt. But doubt is a name;
what do we call by that name? A phenomenon of some complexity, but of which the
elements are not very difficult to trace. There is, here, a double association
with the print of the foot. There is the association of a man, and there is the
association of a monkey. First, the print raises the idea of a man, but the
instant it does so, it raises also the idea of a monkey. The idea of the
monkey, displacing that of the man, hinders the first association from the
fixity which makes it belief; and the idea of man, displacing that of monkey,
hinders the second association from that fixity which constitutes belief.
When evidence is complex; that is, consists of more
than one event; the events may be all on the same side, or not all on the same
side; that is, they may all tend to prove the same event; or some of them may
tend to prove it, some may have an opposite tendency.
Thus, if after discovering the print on the sand, the
sailors had seen near it a stick, which had any appearance of having been
fashioned into a club, or a spear, this would have been another event, tending,
as well as the print on the sand, to the belief of the presence of men. The
evidence would have been complex, but all on one side. The process is easy to
trace. There is now a double association with the existence of men. The print of
the foot excites that idea, the existence of the club excites that idea. This
double excitement gives greater permanence to the idea. By repetition, the two
exciting causes coalesce, and, by their united strength, call up the associated
idea with greater force.
In the case of the appearance of the monkey, in which
one of the events tended to one belief, the other to another, we have just seen
that the effect is precisely contrary; to lessen the strength of the
association with the existence of a man, and to hinder its becoming belief.
These expositions may be applied with ease to the
other cases of complex evidence, which can only consist of a greater or less
number of events, either all tending to the belief of the same event, or some
tending that way, some another; but all operating in the manner which has just
been pointed out. Thus we may complicate the present case still further, by the
supposition of additional events. After the appearance of the monkey, the
sailors may discover, in the neighbourhood, the vestiges of a recent fire, and
of the victuals which had been cooked by it. The association of human beings
with these appearances is so strong, that, combined with the association
between the print and the same idea, it quite obscures the association between
the print and the monkey; and the belief that the place has inhabitants becomes
complete. But suppose, further; that after a little observation, they discover
an English knife, and fork, and a piece of English earthenware near the same
place. The idea of an English ship having touched at the place, is immediately
excited, and all the evidence of local inhabitants, derived from the marks of
fire and cookery, is immediately destroyed. In other words, a new association,
that with an English ship, is created, which completely supersedes the idea,
formerly associated, that of inhabitants existing on the spot.
The whole of the events, which go in this manner to
form a case of belief, or of doubt, or of disbelief, are called Evidence. And
the association, which binds them together into a sort of whole, as antecedent,
and connects with them the event to which they apply as consequent, and which
constitutes the belief, doubt, or disbelief, very often goes by the names of
“judgment,” “judging of the evidence,” “weighing the evidence,” and so on.
In these cases of the belief of Events upon complicated
evidence, there is an antecedent and a consequent; the antecedent consisting of
all the events which are called evidence, the consequent of the event, or
events evidenced; and lastly, there is that close association of the antecedent
and the consequent, which we have seen already, in so many instances,
constitutes belief.
We have now to consider, what we call evidence in the
case of the Belief of Propositions.
There are two cases of the Belief of propositions.
There is belief in the case of the single proposition; and there is belief of
the conclusion of a syllogism, which is the result of a combination of
Propositions.
We have seen what the process of belief in Propositions
is. The subject and predicate, two names for the same thing, of which the
predicate is either of the same extent with the subject, or of a greater
extent, suggests, each of them, its meaning; that is, call up, by association,
each of them, its peculiar cluster of ideas. Two clusters of ideas are called
up in connexion, and that a peculiar connexion, marked by the copula. To have
two clusters of ideas, to know that they are two, and to believe that they are
two, this is nothing more than three expressions for the same thing. To know
that two clusters are two clusters, and to know that they are either the same,
or different, is the same with having them. In this case, then, as in that of
the belief of events, in sense and memory, the belief and the evidence are the
same thing.
Belief of the conclusion of a syllogism, is preceded
by two other beliefs. There is belief of the major proposition; belief of the
minor proposition; by the process immediately above explained, in which the
evidence and the belief are the same thing. These are the antecedent. There is,
thirdly, belief of the conclusion, this is the consequent. The process of this
belief has been so recently explained, that I do not think we need to repeat
it. In this case, it is sometimes said, that the two premises are the evidence;
sometimes it is said, that the ratiocination is the evidence; in the former of
these applications of the word evidence, the belief of the concluding pro
position of the syllogism is not included; in the last, it is. The
ratiocination is the belief of all the three propositions; and, in this
acceptation of the word, the evidence and the belief are not considered as two
things, but one and the same thing. This, however, is only a difference of
naming. About the particulars named, there is no room for dispute. (110)
[110 This chapter on Evidence is supplementary to the
chapter on Belief, and is intended to analyse the process of weighing and
balancing opposing grounds for believing.
Evidence is either of individual facts (not actually
perceived by oneself), or of general truths. The former is the only case to
which much attention is paid in the present chapter; which very happily
illustrates it, by the case of navigators having to decide on the existence or
non-existence of inhabitants in a newly discovered island. The process of
balancing the evidence for and against, is depicted in a very lively manner.
Let us see whether the mental facts set down in the exposition, are precisely
those which take place.
When the sailors have seen prints of a foot,
resembling those of a man, the idea is raised of a man making the print. When
they afterwards see a monkey, whose feet leave traces almost similar, the idea
is also raised of a monkey making the print, and the state of their minds, the
author says, is doubt. Of this state he gives the following analysis: “There is
here a double association with the print of the foot. There is the association
of a man, and there is the association of a monkey. First, the print raises the
idea of a man, but the instant it does so, it raises also the idea of a monkey.
The idea of the monkey, displacing that of the man, hinders the first
association from the fixity which makes it belief; and the idea of man,
displacing that of monkey, hinders the second association from that fixity
which constitutes belief.”
This passage deserves to be studied; for without
having carefully weighed it, we cannot be certain that we are in complete
possession of the author’s theory of Belief.
There are two conflicting associations with the print
of the foot. The picture of a man making it, cannot co-exist with that of a
monkey making it. But the two may alternate with one another. Had the
association with a man been the only association, it would, or might (for on
this point the author is not explicit) have amounted to belief. But the idea of
the monkey and that of the man alternately displacing one another, hinder
either association from having the fixity which would make it belief.
This alternation, however, between the two ideas, of
a monkey making the footprint and of a man making it, may very well take place
without hindering one of the two from being accompanied by belief. Suppose the
sailors to obtain conclusive evidence, testimonial or circumstantial, that the
prints were made by a monkey. It may happen, nevertheless, that the remarkable
resemblance of the foot prints to those of a man, does not cease to force
itself upon their notice: in other words, they continue to associate the idea
of a man with the footsteps; they are reminded of a man, and of a man making
the footsteps, every time they see or think of them. The double association,
therefore, may subsist, and the one which does not correspond with the fact may
even be the most obtrusive of the two, while yet the other conception may be
the one with which the men believe the real facts to have corresponded.
All the rest of the exposition is open to the same
criticism. The author accounts very accurately for the presence of all the
ideas which the successive appearance of the various articles of evidence
arouses in the mind. But he does not shew that the belief, which is ultimately
arrived at, is constituted by the expulsion from the mind of one set of these
ideas, and the exclusive possession of it by the other set. It is quite possible
that neither of the associations may acquire the “fixity” which, according to
the apparent meaning of the author, would defeat the other association
altogether, and drive away the conception which it suggests; and yet, one of
the sup positions may be believed and the other disbelieved, according to the
balance of evidence, as estimated by the investigator. Belief, then, which has
been already shewn not to require an inseparable association, appears not to
require even “fixity”- such fixity as to exclude the idea of the conflicting
supposition, as it does exclude the belief.
The problem of Evidence divides itself into two
distinguishable enquiries: what effect evidence ought to produce, and what
determines the effect that it does produce: how our belief ought to be
regulated, and how, in point of fact, it is regulated. The first enquiry that
into the nature and probative force of evidence: the discussion of what proves
what, and of the precautions needed in admitting one thing as proof of another
are the province of Logic, understood in its widest sense: and for its
treatment we must refer to treatises on Logic, either inductive or
ratiocinative. All that would be in place here, reduces itself to a single
principle: In all cases, except the case of what we are directly conscious of
(in which case, as the author justly observes, the evidence and the belief are
one and the same thing) in all cases, therefore, in which belief is really
grounded on evidence, it is grounded, in the ultimate result, on the constancy
of the course of nature. Whether the belief be of facts or of laws, and whether
of past facts or of those which are present or future, this is the basis on
which it rests. Whatever it is that we believe, the justification of the belief
must be, that unless it were true, the uniformity of the course of nature would
not be maintained. A cause would have occurred, not followed by its invariable
effect; an effect would have occurred, not preceded by any of its invariable
causes; witnesses would have lied, who have always been known to speak the
truth; signs would have proved deceptive, which in human experience have always
given true indication. This is obvious, whatever case of belief on evidence we
examine. Belief in testimony is grounded on previous experience that testimony
is usually conformable to fact: testimony in general (for even this may with
truth be affirmed); or the testimony of the particular witness, or the
testimony of persons similar to him. Belief that the sun will rise and set
to-morrow, or that a stone thrown up into the air will fall back, rests on
experience that this has been invariably the case, and reliance that what has
hitherto occurred will continue to occur hereafter. Belief in a fact vouched
for by circumstantial evidence, rests on experience that such circumstances as
are ascertained to exist in the case, never exist unaccompanied by the given
fact. What we call evidence, whether complete or incomplete, always consists of
facts or events tending to convince us that some ascertained general truths or
laws of nature must have proved false, if the conclusion which the evidence
points to is not true.
Belief on evidence is therefore always a case of the
generalizing process; of the assumption that what we have not directly
experienced resembles, or will resemble, our experience. And, properly
understood, this assumption is true; for the whole course of nature consists of
a concurrence of causes, producing their effects in a uniform manner; but the
uniformity which exists is often not that which our first impressions lead us
to expect. Mr. Bain has well pointed out, that the generalising propensity, in
a mind not disciplined by thought, nor as yet warned by its own failures, far
outruns the evidence, or rather, precedes any conscious consideration of
evidence; and that what the consideration of evidence has to do when it comes,
is not so much to make us generalize, as to limit our spontaneous impulse of
generalization, and restrain within just bounds our readiness to believe that
the unknown will resemble the known. When Mr. Bain occasionally speaks of this
propensity as if it were instinctive, I understand him to mean, that by an
original law of our nature, the mere suggestion of an idea, so long as the idea
keeps possession of the mind, suffices to give it a command over our active
energies. It is to this primitive mental state that the author’s theory of
Belief most nearly applies. In a mind which is as yet untutored, either by the
teachings of others or by its own mistakes, an idea so strongly excited as for
the time to keep out all ideas by which it would itself be excluded, possesses
that power over the voluntary activities which is Mr. Bain’s criterion of
Belief; and any association that compels the person to have the idea of a
certain consequence as following his act. generates, or becomes, a real
expectation of that consequence. But these expectations often turning out to
have been ill grounded, the unduly prompt suggestion comes to be associated, by
repetition, with the shock of disappointed expectation; and the idea of the
desired consequent is now raised together with the idea not of its realization,
but of its frustration: thus neutralizing the effect of the first association
on the belief and on the active impulses. It is in this stage that the mind
learns the habit of looking out for, and weighing, evidence. It presently
discovers that the expectations which are least often disappointed are those
which correspond to the greatest and most varied amount of antecedent experience.
It gradually comes to associate the feeling of disappointed expectation with
all those promptings to expect, which, being the result of accidental
associations, have no, or but little, previous experience conformable to them:
and by degrees the expectation only arises when memory represents a considerable
amount of such previous experience; and is strong in proportion to the quantity
of the experience. At a still later period, as disappointment nevertheless not
unfrequently happens notwithstanding a considerable amount of past experience
on the side of the expectation, the mind is put upon making distinctions in the
kind of past experiences, and finding out what qualities, be sides mere
frequency, experience must have, in order not to be followed by disappointment.
In other words, it considers the conditions of right inference from experience;
and by degrees arrives at principles or rules, more or less accurate, for
inductive reasoning. This is substantially the doctrine of the author of the
Analysis. It must be conceded to him, that an association, sufficiently strong
to exclude all ideas that would exclude itself, produces a kind of mechanical
belief; and that the processes by which this belief is corrected, or reduced to
rational bounds, all consist in the growth of a counter-association, tending to
raise the idea of a disappointment of the first expectation: and as the one or
the other prevails in the particular case, the belief, or expectation, exists
or does not exist, exactly as if the belief were the same thing with the
association. It must also be admitted that the process by which the belief is
overcome, takes effect by weakening the association; which can only be effected
by raising up another association that conflicts with it. There are two ways in
which this counter- association may be generated. One is, by counter-evidence;
by contrary experience in the specific case, which, by associating the
circumstances of the case with a contrary belief, destroys their association
with the original belief. But there is also another mode of weakening, or
altogether destroying, the belief, without adducing contrary experience:
namely, by merely recognising the insufficiency of the existing experience; by
reflecting on other instances in which the same amount and kind of experience
have existed, but were not followed by the expected result. In the one mode as
in the other, the process of dissolving a belief is identical with that of
dissolving an association; and to this extent and it is a very large extent the
author’s theory of Belief must be received as true.
I cannot, however, go beyond this, and maintain with
the author that Belief is identical with a strong association; on account of
the reason already stated, viz. that in many cases indeed in almost all cases
in which the evidence has been such as required to be investigated and weighed
a final belief is arrived at without any such clinging together of ideas as the
author supposes to constitute it; and we remain able to re present to ourselves
in imagination, often with perfect facility, both the conflicting suppositions,
of which we nevertheless believe one and reject the other. Ed.]
No comments:
Post a Comment