© 2012 Norman G. Finkelstein
Published by OR Books, New York and London.
OR Books is a new type of publishing company that
embraces progressive change in politics, culture and the business of
publishing. We sell our books worldwide, direct to readers. To avoid the waste
of unsold copies, we produce our books only when they are wanted, either
through print-on-demand or as platf orm-agnostic e-books. Our approach jettisons
the inefficiencies of conventional publishing to better serve readers, writers
and the environment. If you would like to find out more about OR Books please
visit our website at www.orbooks.com.
First printing 2012.
All rights reserved. No part of this book may be
reproduced or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic or
mechanical, including photocopy, recording, or any information storage
retrieval system, without permission in writing from the publisher, except
brief passages for review purposes.
Cataloging-in-Publication data is available from the
Library of Congress
A catalog record for this book is available from the
British Library
ISBN 978-1-935928-79-9 paperback
ISBN 978-1-935928-80-5 e-book
The typeface in which this book is set is Amalia.
Typeset by Wordstop Technologies, Chennai, India.
Printed by BookMobile in the US and CPI Books Ltd in
the UK. The US printed edition of this book comes on Forest Stewardship
Council-certified, 30% recycled paper. The printer, BookMobile, is 100%
wind-powered.
TABLE OF CONTENTS
Acknowledgments
Introduction
1/ Inner Voice
2/ Death Pillow
3/ Quickened Conscience
4/ People’s Man
Conclusion
Notes
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
I am grateful for the Unz Foundation’s support, and
for the comments on earlier drafts from Samir Chopra, Antony Copley, Meghna Kumar,
Sanjeev Mahajan, Karuna Mantena, Allan Nairn, Abid Qureshi, Marco Rosaire
Rossi, Feroze Sidhwa and Doug Tarnopol. As always, my biggest debt is to my
editor, Maren Hackmann-Mahajan.
INTRODUCTION
Although Mahatma Gandhi’s name is frequently invoked,
he is seldom read.
While checking out his collected works from the
library of a solid American research university, I noticed that of the nearly
100 volumes in the Gandhi corpus, each of which runs to some 500 pages, only
one volume had previously been borrowed.
Gandhi has been reduced to a mantra equating his name
with nonviolence.
But his thought and practice are much more complex,
and contradictory, than this formula suggests.
The Gandhi bequeathed by history is a watered-down,
saccharine version of the original. He is the saintly, otherworldly eccentric
who would not hurt a fly, and looked as if he could not even if he were so
inclined.
The real Gandhi was indeed saintly, otherworldly and
eccentric, but he was also the shrewdest of political tacticians who could
gauge better than any of his contemporaries the reserves and limits of his
people and of his adversaries.
The real Gandhi did loathe violence but he loathed
cowardice more than violence. If his constituents could not find the inner
wherewithal to resist nonviolently, then he exhorted them to find the courage
to hit back those who assaulted or demeaned them.
If Gandhi preached simultaneously the virtues of
nonviolence and courage, it was because he believed that nonviolence required
more courage than violence. The violent combatant faced enemy gunfire with
weapon in hand, whereas the nonviolent resister was expected to march headlong
into enemy fire “smilingly” and “cheerfully” as he was blown to bits. Those who
used nonviolence not to resist but instead as a pretext to flee an assailant
were, according to Gandhi, the most contemptible of human creatures,
undeserving of life.
The controversial Gandhi who valued courage above
nonviolence, who valued nonviolence because it required the maximum reserves of
courage, and who advocated violence if one could not muster this courage, has
been largely forgotten, or effaced.
But even the Gandhi who is remembered perplexes.
The doctrine of satyagraha
that Gandhi propagated was deceptively simple.
It denoted nonviolent resistance to evil, didn’t it?
But Gandhi equated violence with any form of coercive
force.
Still, he counseled the impoverished Indian workers
and peasants to mobilize their latent power
in order to break the will of the exploiting classes.
It was also never quite clear whom Gandhi was trying
to reach with his nonviolent resistance.
Sometimes he spoke about wanting to melt even
Hitler’s heart.
But at other times Gandhi directed his fasts at the
broadly sympathetic public. He undertook to “quicken” its conscience and get it
to act on what it already knew was wrong in order to isolate the handful of
diehards.
This little book attempts to distill the essence of
Gandhi’s doctrine of nonviolent resistance.
Although Gandhi’s preachments are replete with blatant
contradictions, and are informed by a religious faith not always amenable to
rational analysis, it is still possible to tease out a coherent doctrine from
the record he left behind.
But mine is not just, or even primarily, an academic
exercise.
Bringing to bear a keen mind on a rich life
experience of public service, Gandhi extracted valuable practical insights into
the nature of politics, which it would be imprudent to ignore.
I first began to read Gandhi a few years ago in order
to think through a nonviolent strategy for ending the Israeli occupation of
Palestinian lands.
But the field for the application of Gandhi’s ideas
has now been vastly expanded by the emergence of the Arab Spring and nonviolent
resistance movements around the world.
Gandhi’s name is everywhere on the lips of those
challenging a political system that shuts out the overwhelming majority of
people and an economic system that leaves them futureless.
In my own city of New York, the idea of nonviolent
civil disobedience has seized the imagination of young people and energized
them with the hope that they can bring even the ramparts of Wall Street
tumbling down.
Gandhi devoted the whole of his adult life to
organizing the powerless 99 percent against the greedy 1 percent. He aspired in
the first place to end the British occupation of India, but he also recoiled at
the prospect of a corrupt clique of native Indians replacing the foreign
occupiers.
Gandhi sought to lay the foundations for a political
system in which not just nominal but also actual power was transferred to the
Indian masses, and in which wealth was equitably distributed but the chase after
wealth ceased to be life’s purpose.
He was convinced not only that the old world could be
extirpated and a new world be brought into being nonviolently, but also that
unless it was done nonviolently, the new world would hardly differ from the old
world it superseded.
A new generation is now experimenting with and
envisioning novel ways of living, and pondering how to redistribute power and
eliminate privilege. The life experience and reflections of Gandhi provide a
rich trove to help guide these idealistic but disciplined, courageous but
cautious, youth as they venture forth to create a brighter future.
1/INNER VOICE
It is not easy to present a comprehensive or coherent
picture of Gandhi’s doctrine of nonviolent resistance or satyagraha. (1)
As noted in the introduction, Gandhi’s collected
works come to some 100 hefty volumes. I have read about half this corpus, (2)
as well as several anthologies, (3) biographies and scholarly studies. My
remarks will therefore be partial in a single and perhaps double sense. They
will not encompass the full breadth of Gandhi’s reflections. My reading focused
on the period 1930–1947, when Gandhi’s doctrine was put to its severest tests.
But this was also the period when his thinking had fully ripened.
Because of my incomplete reading, I arguably missed
crucial transitions and ruptures in Gandhi’s thought, and consequently I will
have presented a snapshot of a mind at work rather than the moving picture.
But, although he lived a long, rich life, and one relentlessly subjected to
selfscrutiny, Gandhi stayed steadfast in his bedrock beliefs. “Whenever I have
been obliged to compare my writing even of fifty years ago with the latest,” he
observed, “I have discovered no inconsistency between the two.” (4)
Gandhi acknowledged local errors (5) and reversals of
judgment, (6) but there were no “God that Failed” recantations or “Second
Thoughts” epiphanies. His one systematic philosophical exposition is a slim,
seemingly idiosyn cratic volume titled Hind
Swaraj (Indian Home Rule) that he quickly penned in 1909. (7) Reflecting on
this book at various junctures much later in his life, Gandhi expressed full
satisfaction with it. (8)
Still, Gandhi’s life and writings were shot through
with contradictions. He liked to quote Ralph Waldo Emerson, “Foolish
consistency is the hobgoblin of little minds.” (9) It is a misfortune of the little
minds trying to make sense of him that Gandhi was a consistent exponent of this
quip, as he attached little value to consistency: “Charges of ... inconsistency
ought not to matter. What must count with a public servant is the approbation
of his own conscience.” But Gandhi would also insist that he himself was
consistently consistent: “Inconsistency is only apparent. It appears so to many
friends because of my responsiveness to varying circumstances. Seeming
consistency may really be sheer obstinacy.” (10)
The fact is, Gandhi’s actions often did belie his
words. In his defense Gandhi argued that inconsistency was unavoidable in the
application of a theory: “my nonviolence cannot deviate from what is
practical”; “no one is able to act upon a great principle, like that of
nonviolence, in its entirety”; “pure unmixed nonviolence is as impossible as
Euclid’s line.” (11)
At the inception of his political career Gandhi
recruited an ambulance corps for the British side in the Boer and Zulu wars. (12)
He again offered during World War I to mobilize an ambulance corps for the
British army, and then recruited Indians to take up arms and fight alongside
Britain. (13)
The world’s most famous exponent of nonviolence later
even sanctioned “calling in the army and having a handful of men shot” to stop
inter-communal rioting among Indians. (14) Gandhi also acquiesced in India’s
military cooperation with the Allied war effort during World War II if the
British granted it independence, and the deployment of Indian troops after
partition to prevent Kashmir’s secession. (15)
Throughout his life Gandhi would insist that his
active wartime partisanship early in his political life did not contradict his
doctrine of nonviolence. (16) But on this point (and many others) his reasoning
did not carry conviction. (17) Although trained as a barrister, Gandhi was not
a persuasive dialectician. When interrogated by a shrewd critic, he seldom had
a compelling repartee and more often than not lapsed into mumbo-jumbo. “I do
not think that on the whole your argument is coherent,” one of his early
critics fairly observed, “or that the various statements and opinions you
express have any real dependence upon one another.” (18)
But Gandhi did not just fail to acknowledge the gap
between his actions and words. He also resorted to the ex cathedra
pronouncement when the circumstances called for an explanation. To justify his
controversial decision suspending the Salt March, during which millions of
Indians protested the British salt monopoly through tax strikes and civil resistance,
Gandhi simply declared: “It was concluded because it had to be.” (19)
Furthermore, it was not only Gandhi’s actions that
contradicted his words. His statements also, and often flagrantly, contradicted
each other. He could denounce ad nauseam and in broad strokes modern medical
procedures (20) yet still aver that “the West has always commanded my
admiration [for] its surgical inventions and all-round progress in that
direction.” (21) He could contend that “in any examination of moral conduct,
the intention is the chief ingredient,” and simultaneously contend that “a man
must be judged by his action, not the motive prompting it.” (22) He could
deplore as a species of violence “a living wall of pickets in order to prevent
the entry of persons into picketed places,” (23) yet at the same time advise an
Indian correspondent, whose seat was snatched by a British soldier at the
cinema, that he should “deliberately so to stand as to obstruct the view of the
usurper.” (24) He could state in one breath that even in “the classical
instance of the defenseless sister or mother who is threatened with molestation
by an evil-minded ruffian,” resort to violence would not be justifiable, (25)
yet in the next breath “defend” use of violence “against the whole world if I
found myself in a corner when I could not save a helpless girl from violation.”
(26)
Gandhi could avow during World War II that his
“sympathies are wholly with the Allies” because “this war is resolving itself
into one between such democracy as the West has evolved and totalitarianism as
it is typified in Hitler,” that “There is a fundamental difference between
Fascism and even this [British] imperialism which I am fighting,” and right after
World War II that “a victory for the Axis would have been far worse. The Axis
had accepted violence as their creed. The Allies had not done so. They at least
paid lip service to peace and freedom, and truth and nonviolence.” (27) Yet, he
could more or less concurrently avow that “Hitlerism and Churchillism are in
fact the same thing,” and that “I must fight Nazism and Fascism equally with
the enslaving British imperialism.” (28) He could praise the decision of French
leaders not to resist Nazi aggression because “the cause of liberty becomes a
mockery if the price to be paid is wholesale destruction of those who are to
enjoy liberty,” yet he could also assert that “no greater evil can befall a
country than that it should lose its independence,” (29) and that nations
occupied by the Nazis should choose annihilation rather than cooperate with the
occupiers. (30)
Humble as he indubitably was, Gandhi nonetheless
always seemed to believe, mistakenly, that he had bested detractors who pointed
out an inconsistency of his. But it must also be said that he never shied away
from giving critics of his pronouncements and policies a fair hearing. In
conveying an intellectual or political dispute, he did not rig its terms to
favor him or create straw men.
If Gandhi was more inconsistent than he let on, it
should perhaps also be recalled that Gandhi conceived himself as “essentially a
man of action and a reformer,” a “practical idealist,” “a man of action” for
whom “logic comes afterwards, it does not precede the event,” and “not built
for academic writings. Action is my domain.” (31) Intellectual coherence and
rigor figured as low priorities compared to getting things done. (32) He
accordingly urged interlocutors who detected “inconsistencies, so-called or
real” in this or that pronouncement of his to examine each one solely on its
own “merits and bless the effort if they can.” (33)
While taking note of Gandhi’s vacillations, it also
bears repeating that his accommodation to circumstance went hand-in-hand with a
rare faithfulness to principle. Were he just another pragmatic politician,
Gandhi could not have won the devotion of India’s impoverished masses. “I claim
to be a practical idealist. I believe in compromise.” But only, Gandhi qualified,
“so long as it does not involve the sacrifice of principles.” (34) On one of
these core beliefs, truth-telling, Gandhi avowed, “There never can be an
occasion when one must tell a lie. If there can be such an occasion, then it
would follow that the principle of following truth in speech and action was
imperfect. There can be no exception to a principle, and hence there can be no
atonement for untruth spoken knowingly.” (35) Like everyone else, Gandhi no
doubt succumbed to self-deception, but unlike almost anyone else, and corny as
it might sound and dubious as it might appear, he probably never consciously
lied.
It is not just because of Gandhi’s many flip-flops,
however, that one is hard-pressed to distill from his life’s work a coherent
doctrine. He could also be superficial, flippant and downright arrogant. Gandhi
passed sweeping verdicts on topics such as socialism, although conceding that
“I have read no books on the subject,” (36) and on motion pictures, which he
did “not like,” although admitting that “I have never gone to a cinema.” (37)
He could issue statements on behalf of the “All-India Women’s Conference” to
its British “sisters,” and declare before an audience of women that “I know
your sex and your needs better than you do yourselves.” (38)
Additionally, Gandhi never bothered to produce a
systematic handbook on satyagraha
because, according to him, to “live it” and “practice the idea in my own life”
better conveyed its meaning. (39) One has to piece together his doctrine from
scattered and not only incongruous but also confusing and obscure fragments.
What confounds yet more, Gandhi blithely conflated
categories and collapsed critical distinctions. He made it appear as if he were
uniformly applying one simple doctrine, whereas in fact it was a subtly differentiated
one. He directed his appeal, depending on the occasion, to qualitatively different
audiences. Sometimes he strove to “melt the heart” of the actual malefactor
into submission, sometimes he strove to “quicken the conscience” of the passive
bystander into action. By the same token, he sought to convert his audience,
depending on the occasion, via qualitatively different tactics. Sometimes he
used moral suasion, but sometimes he used coercive force, although he subsumed
both these tactics under the same, deceptively benign rubric of nonviolence.
What makes a rational account of Gandhi’s doctrine
most elusive, however, is that it was steeped in religious faith. “It is faith
that sustains me,” he intoned, “and it is faith that must sustain the other
satyagrahis”; “The root of satyagraha
is in prayer.” But Gandhi’s doctrine was not just born of faith. He also
explicitly counterposed it to one grounded in reason: “Faith is not a question
of reason. It comes from within”; “My thinking nowadays takes the form
exclusively of prayer. I do not use my reason, but look into my heart.” (40)
Although eager to recruit satyagrahis for the struggle, Gandhi was emphatic
that communists and other nonbelievers need not apply, because “real love for
man I regard to be utterly impossible without love for God.” (41)
When Gandhi embarked on a civil disobedience
campaign, a fast, or negotiations, it was not—at any rate, not
self-consciously—after a material reckoning of the “balance of forces,” but
instead after an “inner urge,” “inner voice,” or “giftfrom God” prompted him.
“I am not guided by reason,” he avowed, “but by instinct or in other words by
the inner voice and one never knows where that voice would lead you to”; “I do
not depend upon my intellect to decide upon any action. For me the reasoned
course of action is held in check subject to the sanction of the inner voice.”
(42) It should be obvious that, on such a basis, the movement Gandhi built
could not but be authoritarian: How does one argue with an “inner voice”?
Gandhi denoted satyagraha
a “science,” (43) and conceived it not as a closed system but, in scientific
spirit, as ceaseless experimentation in a perpetual and always incomplete
search for truth. Still, his was a “science” not amenable to external proof or
refutation; its power sprang from the “efficacy of the incalculable force of
inscrutable divinity.” (44) If ahimsa (nonviolence) did not produce the desired
outcome, this demonstrated not an inadequacy in the science but an impurity
lurking in its human agent: “Ahimsa is always infallible. When, therefore, it
appears to have failed, the failure is due to the inaptitude of the votary.” (45)
Gandhi might have been right, but it is hard to figure how one could have
proven him wrong, just as one could not answer, because they were literally
unanswerable, his Olympian pronouncements and saccharine bromides such as
nonviolence, buoyed by the intervention of God, being the most potent force in
the world. (46)
In principle Gandhi praised “independent thinking” as
the “very essence of the spirit of democracy.” He professed, “It is certainly
not my wish, nor is it desirable, that everyone who comes close to me should be
like me in every respect. That would mean mechanical imitation”; “I do not wish
to make everybody like me. My teaching is that everybody should be true to
himself”; “I ask no one to follow me. Each should go by the voice within ...
you must on no account blindly follow anybody.” (47)
Nonetheless Gandhi asserted a proprietary right over
nonviolent resistance because he was the “sole authority on satyagraha,” “most
experienced satyagrahi,” and “author of satyagraha
and general in satyagraha action.” (48)
And inasmuch as he was, or conceived himself to be, uniquely privy to the
mysteries of satyagraha, no one had title to argue with him about it: “I think
and feel that it is God within Who is moving me and using me as His
instrument”; “I am confident that God has made me the instrument of showing the
better way.” (49) Put simply, to doubt Gandhi was to doubt God.
If one challenged Gandhi’s judgment, it could only be
because the skeptic had “superficial knowledge” of satyagraha, which
furthermore could not be helped “because this philosophy could not be studied
from books.” (50) And if Gandhi knew better, it was because of his unmatched
“achievement based on forty years’ experience.” (51) One could march behind Gandhi,
or choose not to.
One could not, however, decide on a course of action
beside yet despite him. Thus he would proclaim, “There is a rule that no one
should go on a fast without my permission”; “If we want to work nonviolently,
then it is necessary to accept the restrictions laid down by me”; “Anyone whose
fast is related to satyagraha should
seek my permission and obtain it in writing before embarking on it. If this
advice is followed, there is no need for framing rules, at any rate, in my
lifetime”; “Fasting for a public cause also has its shastra [specialized or
technical knowledge] and I am the only one adequately versed in it.” (52) On
other occasions Gandhi counseled his disciples not to fear thinking and acting
for themselves, but only because he would be around to correct their errors. (53)
Gandhi eschewed all sectarian “isms,” including
“Gandhism.” “I love to hear the words: ‘Down with Gandhism,’” he declared. “An
‘ism’ deserves to be destroyed.” (54) But the alternative he offered often had
the feel of autocratic whimsy. Gandhi had a party line not just on sexual
abstinence and vegetarianism, but also on “idle jokes” (opposed), “innocent
pleasantries” (perhaps), wrist watches (opposed), underwear (opposed),
conversing while at work (opposed), and pencils and fountain pens (opposed). (55)
He sometimes sounded like Stalin pronouncing on linguistics, albeit in his case
deviationists might be banished from his ashram but not deported to the Gulag.
(56)
The bottom line is that much of Gandhi’s doctrine was
inseparable from his person and personality. Still, it was much less arbitrary
and much more coherent than he sometimes made it sound.
In any exposition of satyagraha, it must also be remembered that Gandhi did not conceive
nonviolent resistance as the heart of his doctrine. He situated satyagraha in a matrix of daily
activities, what he called the “constructive program,” that formed the
“foundation for civil disobedience.” Its planks included expunging from
Hinduism the “blot” of untouchability, fostering Hindu-Muslim unity, and
promoting use on a mass scale of the spinning wheel (tcharka) and handspun cloth (khadi).
On this practical basis, Gandhi believed, Indians
could forge unbreakable bonds of unbounded love that transcended sect and class.
Once Indians adhered to the constructive program, Gandhi further prophesized,
complete self-rule (purna swaraj)
would drop like a ripe fruit into India’s lap and political confrontation with
Great Britain would be unnecessary, while the nonviolent future of India would
be safeguarded: “If we learn to love one another, if the gulf between Hindu and
Muslim, caste and outcaste, and rich and poor is obliterated, a handful of
English would not dare to continue their rule over us.” (57)
In conclusion, it must be conceded that Gandhi would
almost certainly have questioned my goal in writing this book. He was firmly
wedded to the belief that a rational core of satyagraha could not be separated out from its spiritual essence:
“It is impossible that a thing essentially of the soul can be imparted through
the intellect.” (58)
I am nonetheless convinced that Gandhi has important
things to say on the subject of nonviolent resistance, from which even the most
resolute secularist would greatly benefit, and that the content of his doctrine
can be accessed by reason and made accessible to the rational mind. It will be
for the reader to decide whether I am right.
2/DEATH PILLOW
What is satyagraha?
The “votaries” of nonviolent civil resistance,
according to Gandhi, have to purge themselves of any and all aggressive
impulses. They “must not be violent in thought, word or deed,” in fact, must be
“incapable of feeling or harboring anger.” (1)
The essence of Gandhi’s creed is not, however, a
negative “non”-principle but the affirmative or “active” principle of
“unadulterated love—fellow-feeling,” which in turn springs from “faith in the
inherent goodness of human nature,” and the belief that “what holds good in
respect of yourself holds good equally in respect of the whole universe. All
mankind in essence are alike.” (2) If even one person is unimpeachably loving
and good, then we all are.
True, the annals of humankind appear rife with
violence. But, Gandhi contended, this was an optical illusion fostered by
scribes and scholars who, by virtue of their profession, took note of the
exceptions to the rule: “History is really a record of every interruption of
the even working of the force of love or of the soul.” (3)
“The law of love,” Gandhi professed, “rules mankind.”
Were it otherwise, we would not still be around: “The fact that mankind
persists shows that the cohesive force is greater than the disruptive force,
centripetal force greater than centrifugal”; “Had violence, i.e., hate, ruled
us, we should have become extinct long ago”; “If the sum-total of the world’s
activities was destructive, it would have come to an end long ago.” (4)
Just as “families or even clans” manage to resolve
conflicts nonviolently through the binding powers of love, so can “humankind,”
which is “one big family.” (5) To illustrate love’s power to overcome violent
tyranny, Gandhi often pointed to the metamorphosis in his own spousal
relations: although “I literally used to make life a hell for her,” eventually
“her guileless simplicity conquered me completely.” (6)
Gandhi’s faith in the inherent goodness of humankind
could stretch credulity to its limits. In 1940 he wrote a “Dear Friend” letter
to Hitler in which he averred not “to believe that you are the monster
described by your opponents,” albeit acknowledging that “many of your acts are
monstrous and unbecoming of human dignity.” (7)
Because love is at its core, satyagraha eschews violence. It also eschews inflicting indirect,
non-physical, quasi forms of coercion such as fear, lying, and embarrassment. (8)
Gandhi additionally denounced assaults on property or even scaling walls
enclosing private property as “pure violence.” (9)
Unlike violence, which “obtains reforms by external
means,” satyagraha, according to
Gandhi, relied exclusively on the internal method of “self-purification” that
came of self-suffering: “the more innocent and pure the suffering the more
potent will it be in its effect.” (10) The purpose of such self-sacrifice was
to arouse from its slumber the conscience of wrongdoers in order “to convert,
not to coerce” them, and the conscience of sympathetic bystanders in order to
galvanize them into action. (11)
The greater the number of satyagrahis ready to sacrifice
themselves, and the more unalloyed their motives, Gandhi declared during the Salt
March, the sooner victory would be theirs: “Unless thousands die, swaraj [independence] ... will not be
secured. The purer the men sacrificing themselves in this cause, the earlier
shall we get swaraj and the less will
be the number of people sacrificed”; “Nothing will be better than if this band
of satyagrahis perishes.” (12) A satyagrahi’s ultimate sacrifice,
according to Gandhi, not only pricked the public’s conscience but also “purifies
those left behind and awakens a greater spirit of service.” (13) In another
version, he pointed to the transforming powers not of self-suffering per se but
of the “upwelling of love and pity towards the wrongdoer.” (14)
Gandhi censured resort to violence on both personal
and political, and both moral and pragmatic, grounds. It corrupted the
individual, who was degraded to the level of a beast: “That which distinguishes
man from all other animals is his capacity to be nonviolent.” (15) But it also
tainted the goal of an enlightened politics. Means and ends, he suggested in an
evocative simile, were inextricably intertwined: “The means may be likened to a
seed, the end to a tree.” Consequently, however just the cause, the resort to
violence as a political weapon would always and inevitably place the “powerful
and mighty” at the apex of a hierarchy, while the “blind, the halt and the
maimed” remain disenfranchised: “violence may destroy one or more bad rulers,
but ... others will pop up in their places.” (16)
Gandhi further contended that any victory achieved
through violence would be fleeting: “a man who yields to threat or physical
coercion resents it and simply awaits a suitable opportunity to revert to his
original ways and resorts to reprisals when he is able to exact them.” (17)
The recourse to violent means also excluded from
political participation those unwilling or unable to wield it, but without whom
the struggle could not be won:
Do you think that all the women and the children who
covered themselves with glory during the last campaign [Salt March] would have
done so if we had pursued the path of violence? Would they have been here
today? Would our women, known as the meekest on earth, would women like
Gangabehn, who stood the lathi-blows until her white sari was drenched in
blood, have done the unique service they did if we had violence in us? With
God’s name on their lips, she and her sisters hurled defiance at their
oppressors, without anger in their hearts. And our children—our vanarasena
(monkey-army). How could you have had these innocent ones, who renounced their
toys, their kites and their crackers, and joined as soldiers of swaraj—how
could you have enlisted them in a violent struggle? We were able to enlist as
soldiers millions of men, women and children because we were pledged to
nonviolence. (18)
On other occasions Gandhi would pragmatically argue
that, whereas violence was perhaps a viable option elsewhere, “terrorism is the
very worst thing for India in a special manner, because India is a foreign soil
for terrorism to flourish in.” (19)
Even, or especially, in the face of the ruthless Axis
aggression during World War II, according to Gandhi, the use of armed force was
to be eschewed. If the Allies did manage to inflict a military defeat on the
Axis, it could only be by becoming “stronger than they are, and therefore worse
and more ruthless”; “that would mean no deliverance from Nazism,” but “superior
Nazism.” (20) Victor would come to resemble, and consequently would in effect
be, vanquished, while “such a victory must mean another preparation for a war
more inhuman than the present, as this one had proved more inhuman than the
last.” (21)
On many counts Gandhi’s diagnosis and prognosis
appear wanting. Although committing many atrocities, the Allied states coming
out of World War II did not mirror, let alone surpass, Nazi Germany in
brutality. Nonetheless, even after the war ended, Gandhi was unrepentant on
this point: “the United Nations set out to fight Hitler with his weapons and
ended by out-Hitlering Hitler”; “what had happened in Europe was that Hitlerism
had only been destroyed by super- Hitlerism”; “whilst the enemy powers
so-called were crushed, the Allied Powers had won but an empty victory. Apart
from the wanton destruction of human heads, they had—between the Allies and the
enemies—succeeded in draining the world of its food materials and cloth. And
the former seemed to be so dehumanized that they had entertained the vain hope
of reducing the enemies to helotry. It was a question whom to pity more—the
Allies or the enemies.” (22)
In addition Gandhi posited that nonviolent resistance
could not produce inferior results to violent resistance. “Either the enemy
comes to terms with you, then you win without blood,” he reasoned, “or the enemy
annihilates you. This last solution is not worse than what a violent war in any
case brings about.” (23) Gandhi willfully ignored the third possibility that
violent resistance could defeat the Nazis short of one’s annihilation, albeit
at a terrible human cost, which is, of course, what happened. It is more difficult
to gainsay Gandhi’s assertion that, once having imitated Nazi methods, a cause
“cannot be called just,” (24) except to conjure up pedantic and morally obtuse
distinctions between Auschwitz and Hiroshima.
But, however much he deplored violence, Gandhi did
not unreservedly oppose it. (25) In the first place, he did not categorize
forceful resistance in the face of impossible odds—a woman fending off a rapist
with her bare hands, an unarmed man resisting torture by a gang, Polish armed
self-defense in the face of the Nazi aggression—as violence. In his reckoning
such resort to force was largely symbolic and instinctive, akin to the
“struggling of a mouse against a cat.” In the instance of a rape victim, her
“slap or scratching” manifested the “resolve” to “offer up ... body and life,
but ... not become a coward.... It is in itself an act of nonviolence. She has
no strength to cause harm”; the “slap rouses oneself, makes oneself fearless
and above all, gives oneself the strength to die.” (26)
Furthermore, until and unless he converted others to
his beliefs, Gandhi accepted that only the prevailing morallegal norms bound
the actions of individuals. Thus, while personally renouncing it, he did
acknowledge the legitimacy of resort to violence in a righteous cause:
“self-defense is everybody’s birthright.” (27)
In the face of personal insult and “if you feel
humiliated,” Gandhi opined, sounding more like Malcolm X than Martin Luther
King, “you will be justified in slapping the bully in the face or taking
whatever action you might deem necessary to vindicate your self-respect.” (28)
And although “not defending the Arab excesses” during the 1936–1939 Arab Revolt
in Palestine, and although “wishing they had chosen the way of nonviolence in
resisting what they rightly regarded as an unwarrantable encroachment upon
their country,” Gandhi nonetheless maintained that “according to the accepted
canons of right and wrong, nothing can be said against the Arab resistance in
the face of overwhelming odds.” (29)
Gandhi and Palestine
Gandhi rejected the ideological tenets underpinning
the Zionist colonization of Palestine. He did not accept that Jews had a
biblical title to Palestine, and instead counseled them to seek their rights in
the countries where they resided. If Jews did decide to go to Palestine, it had
to be with the consent of the indigenous population. Otherwise, “they are cosharers
with the British in despoiling a people who have done no wrong to them.” (30)
Late in life Gandhi was seemingly less critical of the Jews’ aspiration to settle
in Palestine, but he still deplored that they were “seeking to impose
themselves on Palestine with the aid of America and Britain and now with the
aid of naked terrorism.” (31) A cottage industry has sprung up trying to prove
that what Gandhi repeatedly said on Palestine and Zionism he did not really
mean. (32) The scholarly output is long on speculation and rich in digression,
but precious short on substantiating evidence.
On comparable grounds, although personally opposing
“punishment” for lawbreakers because it was a species of violence, Gandhi still
acquiesced in the practice because “governments functioning today are based on
the theory of punishment.” He even appeared to sanction shooting those guilty
of treason because “Everywhere in the world traitors are shot down as a rule.”
(33)
But Gandhi did not just extenuate violence on
circumstantial grounds. (34) He also positively advocated it if, in the face of an injustice, the only other
options were abject surrender or retreat. Gandhi detested “mute submissiveness”
(35) more than violence and, what was yet more sinful in his eyes, such
subjection masquerading as nonviolent resistance. Should one be incapable of
nonviolently resisting an outrage, then the only honorable recourse would be to
resist violently, whereas flight would be wholly shameful.
Gandhi ranked not violence but pusillanimity and effeminacy
as the worst personal failings and the most egregious “shortcoming” of Indians,
while he prized the qualities of courage and manliness: “nonviolence is the
greatest virtue, cowardice the greatest vice”; “the fundamental thing to be
borne in mind is that people should, under no circumstances, be cowardly or
impotent”; “it is unmanly to run away from danger.” (36) Gandhi tersely defined
the “aim of the satyagraha struggle”
he led in South Africa as being “to infuse manliness in cowards.” (37)
Ironically, on the very rare occasions when Gandhi
used brutal language, he directed it not at those who practiced violence but
instead at those who feared it: “Cowardice is impotence worse than violence.
The coward desires revenge but being afraid to die, he looks to others, maybe
the Government of the day, to do the work of defense for him. A coward is less than a man. He does not
deserve to be a member of a society of men and women”; “[Those who]
continued to look to the police and the military for help ... would remain
slaves for ever. Those who preferred security to freedom had no right to live.” (38) One who refrained from shedding blood
because of fear effectively stood lower on Gandhi’s moral hierarchy than one
who would shed it in bucket loads. Indeed, in his moral calculus, cowardice
constituted the ultimate manifestation of violence: “Doing injury to another is
obviously violence, but harboring injury to another and yet unwillingness from
cowardice to defend oneself or one’s neighbor is also violence, and proba bly
worse than the first.” (39)
If Gandhi despised one thing more than cowardice, it
was cowardice wrapping itself in the mantle of nonviolence. He was emphatic
that if one could not summon the inner resources to be nonviolent, then
forceful retaliation was not only justified but also imperative, while flight
in the name of nonviolence was contemptible. Gandhi’s collected works are
filled with, on the one hand, scalding condemnations of ersatz nonviolence and,
on the other, exhortations to violence if the only other option is craven
retreat. Strangely, they echo and recall the imagery of Nietzsche’s acid
critique of Christian “slave morality” that inverts weakness into a virtue
while devaluing courage and strength. Consider the representative passages
below.
I Can Only Prefer
Violence to Cowardice
1920
Where there is only a choice between cowardice and
violence, I would advise violence. Thus when my eldest son asked me what he
should have done, had he been present when I was almost fatally assaulted in
1908, whether he should have run away and seen me killed or whether he should
have used his physical force, which he could and wanted to use, and defended
me, I told him that it was his duty to defend me even by using violence....
Hence ... I advocate training in arms for those who believe in the method of
violence. I would rather have India resort to arms in order to defend her honor
than that she should in a cowardly manner become or remain a helpless witness
to her own dishonor. But I believe that nonviolence is infinitely superior to
violence, forgiveness is more manly than punishment.... But abstinence is
forgiveness only when there is the power to punish; it is meaningless where it
pretends to proceed from a helpless creature. A mouse hardly forgives a cat
when it allows itself to be torn to pieces by her. (40)
1924
My nonviolence does not admit of running away from
danger and leaving dear ones unprotected. Between violence and cowardly flight,
I can only prefer violence to cowardice. I can no more preach nonviolence to a
coward than I can tempt a blind man to enjoy healthy scenes. Nonviolence is the
summit of bravery. And in my own experience, I have had no difficulty in
demonstrating to men trained in the school of violence the superiority of
nonviolence. As a coward, which I was for years, I harbored violence. I began
to prize nonviolence only when I began to shed cowardice. Those Hindus who ran
away from the post of duty when it was attended with danger did so not because
they were nonviolent, or because they were afraid to strike, but because they
were unwilling to die or even suffer any injury. A rabbit that runs away from
the bull terrier is not particularly nonviolent. The poor thing trembles at the
sight of the terrier and runs for very life. Those Hindus who ran away to save
their lives would have been truly nonviolent and would have covered themselves
with glory and added luster to their faith and won the friendship of their
Mussalman assailants, if they had stood bare breast with smiles on their lips,
and died at their post. They would have done less well, though still well, if
they had stood at these posts and returned blow for blow. If the Hindus wish to
convert the Mussalman bully into a respecting friend, they have to learn to die
in the face of the heaviest odds. (41)
1935
Nonviolence cannot be taught to a person who fears to
die and has no power of resistance. A helpless mouse is not nonviolent because
he is always eaten by [a] pussy[cat]. He would gladly eat the murderess if he
could, but he ever tries to flee from her. We do not call him a coward, because
he is made by nature to behave no better than he does. But a man who, when
faced by danger, behaves like a mouse, is rightly called a coward. He harbors
violence and hatred in his heart and would kill his enemy if he could without
being hurt himself. He is a stranger to nonviolence. All sermonizing on it will
be lost on him. Bravery is foreign to his nature. Before he can understand
nonviolence he has to be taught to stand his ground and even suffer death in
the attempt to defend himself against the aggressor who bids fair to overwhelm
him. To do otherwise would be to confirm his cowardice and take him further
away from nonviolence. Whilst I may not actually help anyone to retaliate, I
must not let a coward seek shelter behind nonviolence so-called. Not knowing
the stuff of which nonviolence is made many have honestly believed that running
away from danger every time was a virtue compared to offering resistance,
especially when it is fraught with danger to one’s life. As a teacher of
nonviolence I must, so far as it is possible for me, guard against such an
unmanly belief.... Self-defense ... is the only honorable course where there is
unreadiness for self-immolation. (42)
1939
For I cannot in any case stand cowardice. Let no one
say when I am gone that I taught the people to be cowards. If you think my
ahimsa amounts to that, or leads you to that, you should reject it without
hesitation. I would far rather that you died bravely dealing a blow and
receiving a blow than died in abject terror.... Fleeing from battle ... is
cowardice, and unworthy of a warrior. An armed fighter is known to have sought
fresh arms as soon as he loses those in his possession or they lose their efficacy.
He leaves the battle to get them. A nonviolent warrior knows no leaving the battle.
He rushes into the mouth of himsa [violence], never even once harboring an evil
thought. If this ahimsa seems to you to be impossible, let us be honest with
ourselves and say so, and give it up.... Cowardice is worse than violence
because cowards can never be nonviolent. So such people should learn to defend
themselves.... A person who has full faith in nonviolence should be a thousand
times more fearless than an armed man.... It is the duty of every believer in
ahimsa to see that cowardice is not propagated in the name of nonviolence. (43)
These passages, which span the gamut of Gandhi’s
public life, strike identical chords: nonviolence born of fear is cowardice;
cowardice is worse than violence; violent retaliation is morally superior to
fear-inspired abstention.
The authentic spirit of nonviolence and the warrior
spirit, Gandhi paradoxically suggested, both sprang from the identical source:
fearlessness. He heaped praise on the “reckless courage” of soldiers on the battlefield,
and wanted “to learn ... the art of throwing away my life for a noble cause.” (44)
He held up the “example of Sparta,” because “though they were an armed people
and also few, they laid down their lives but would not leave their places.” (45)
He drew inspiration from the typical “Pathan [Pashtun] boy” because he is
“fearless. If there is bloodshed he does not hide himself in his house. He finds
pleasure in fighting. He does not stop to think that he might be injured or
even killed. He is never afraid of being hurt. I have seen one standing unmoved
in the midst of blood gushing from his many wounds.” (46)
Inversely, Gandhi chastised (albeit mistakenly)
German Jews for pretending to nonviolence yet seeking violent revenge on the
Nazis: “There is no nonviolence in their hearts. Their nonviolence, if it may
be so called, is of the helpless and the weak.” (47) Likewise, Gandhi rebuked
the cowardice of his disciples who elected milder, to evade severer, sanctions:
“The nonviolence of the person who went to jail to avoid a worse fate harmed
him and disgraced the cause which he used as a shelter to escape death.” (48)
But Gandhi also candidly confessed his own failure to
meet the heroic standard he set. (49) He attributed this gap between ideal and
practice to his intellectual acceptance of death but his emotional recoiling
from it. (50) Still, in the last year of his life Gandhi seemingly wanted to
die at his post. Because he wanted to demonstrate in his own person that it was
possible to court death consciously and to accept it serenely. Because he
believed that “the greatest bravery lies in having the courage to die.” (51)
And because he had dispatched so many of his disciples to their deaths, and
even demanded of them that they get themselves killed, during the
inter-communal fighting. In response to local leaders who solicited his advice
on how to end the internecine bloodletting, Gandhi counseled: “Go in the midst
of the rioters and prevent them from indulging in madness or get killed in the
attempt. But do not come back alive to report failure. The situation calls for
sacrifice on the part of top-rankers.” (52)
While enthralled by battlefield heroics, Gandhi
professed that the satyagrahi had to
bring forth yet greater reserves of inner courage than the armed combatant: “I
believe that a man is the strongest soldier for daring to die unarmed with his
breast bare before the enemy”; “To die without killing requires more heroism.
There is nothing very wonderful in killing and being killed in the process. But
the man who offers his neck to the enemy for execution but refuses to bend to
his will shows courage of a far higher type.” (53)
It was incumbent upon satyagrahis to accept, indeed relish, the prospect of mutely
subjecting themselves to mass slaughter. “Such an army should be ready to cope
with any emergency,” Gandhi declared amid inter-communal fi ghting, “and in
order to still the frenzy of mobs, should risk their lives in numbers sufficient
for the purpose. A few hundred, maybe a few thousand, such spotless deaths will
once and for all put an end to the riots.” And they must not draw back from the
fate awaiting them: “if we are to train ourselves to receive the bullet wounds
or bayonet charges in our bare chests, we must accustom ourselves to standing
unmoved in the face of cavalry or baton charges.” (54)
In stirring phrases Gandhi called upon his disciples
to march headlong, unarmed yet “smilingly” and “cheerfully,” into the valley of
death, while earnestly praying, “May good befall him who kills me!” (55) He
posited that the more one internalized the true spirit of nonviolence born of
fearlessness, the less inclined one would be to exact revenge: “When a man is
fully ready to die he will not even desire to offer violence ... the desire to
kill is in inverse proportion to the desire to die.” (56) Of which, it might be
said, Gandhi’s own death was exemplary.
“Wherein is courage required,” Gandhi rhetorically
asked, “in blowing others to pieces from behind a cannon, or with a smiling
face to approach a cannon and to be blown to pieces? Who is the true warrior—he
who keeps death always as a bosom-friend or he who controls the death of
others?” (57) “What I shall expect of you,” he lectured the “officers” of his
army, “is that even if someone subjects you to the most inhuman tortures, you
will joyfully face the ordeal and make the supreme sacrifice with God’s name on
your lips and without a trace of fear or anger or thoughts of revenge in your
hearts.” (58) And in a macabre peroration, he avowed, “That nation is great
which rests its head upon death as its pillow.” (59)
It might fairly be said that Gandhi fostered a death
cult. Consider the representative passages assembled below. His cavalier indifference
to life and morbid embrace of death are the most unappealing and incoherent
facets of his doctrine.
It Would Exhilarate Me to
Hear That a Coworker Was Shot Dead
Whilst therefore I tender my sympathy to the parents
of the two brave lads who lost their lives [he said after the murder of these
disciples], my inmost desire is to congratulate them for the finished sacrifices
of their sons, if they would accept my congratulations. A warrior’s death is
never a matter of sorrow, still less that of a satyagrahi warrior. One of the
lessons that a nation yearning for freedom needs to learn is to shed several
fears; fear of losing title, wealth, position, fear of imprisonment, of bodily
injury and lastly of death. (60)
I attach no value now to jail-going. I feel no
exhilaration when I hear that some coworker of mine was sentenced to one year
or two years, or, for that matter, even five years. It would exhilarate me to
hear that a coworker like Jairamdas was shot dead or that another coworker, of
an equally spotless character, had had his skull broken.... If Ramniklal had
made an offering of his head and a patch of Bulsar land had been besmeared with
his blood, then you would have been justified in asking me to come.... Such
heroism is being displayed at Anand and at Dehwan. There volunteers were beaten
up in the night and, so that the police might enjoy beating them, lights were
put out. If they call me there, I would immediately go. There is an occasion
worth celebrating. (61)
Two Hindu workers and a Muslim worker set out to
quell the riots and died in the effort. I am not unhappy at their death. I do
not weep for them. Ganesh Shankar Vidyarthi laid down his life similarly in the
Kanpur riots.... I was happy at his death. I do not say all this to excite you.
I want to make you understand that if you but learn how to die all will be
well. (62)
Gandhi would even balk at extending condolences on
receipt of a death notice. (See the columns below for Gandhi’s typical
acknowledgments.) Instead, he waxed philosophical that birth and death are
inevitable and complementary stages in nature’s cycle, “one and the same
thing.” (63) Far from being cause for sorrow or dread, death for Gandhi was “a
necessary and beneficial phenomenon,” “a deliverance,” “that inevitable and
grand event,” a “boon,” “a friend. What would we have done if there were no
Death?” (64)
Why Grieve over Anyone’s
Death?
There is not the slightest reason to be grieved by
the death of friends. None ever dies before his time. The notion of untimely
death is a delusion. Even the death of a day-old baby is not an untimely one.
It only means that the actions to be performed through that body had been
performed. We feel pained by death only because of our ignorance and selfishness.
We feel agitated over the death of friends or others because of our ignorance
of the soul’s attributes and because we do not wish ourselves to die. (65)
Why do you feel so unhappy? After all, no great
tragedy has struck you down. There is no law that no one shall die young.
Moreover, you and I have not one child, but countless children. Some of them
will die and others will be born to take their place. Why, then, keep count of
who dies and who lives? (66)
To mourn the death of either son or husband is
meaningless and shows our ignorance. This should not be dismissed as merely
wise talk; it is a truth to be pondered over till it sinks into our heart and
to be acted upon. Since death is certain for all, the only question is whether
it comes today or tomorrow. Why, then, should we grieve over anyone’s death? It
is only the body which dies. That is its nature and therefore there is no cause
for wonder when it dies. It is certain that the soul which dwells in the body
never dies, it is immortal. When we know this as certain truth, why should we
grieve over death? (67)
If Gandhi truly believed this, and there seems no
reason not to take him at his word, it forces one to wonder why he considered
nonviolence so sacred a calling: by his reckoning, to kill someone is just not
such a big deal. Furthermore, if life and death are mere ephemera in nature’s
eternal cycle, why should a satyagrahi’s
willingness to die prick anyone’s conscience, and why should it be judged
heroic if a satyagrahi wills his
death?
The ideal satyagrahi,
according to Gandhi, marches smilingly and cheerfully into the line of fire and
gets blown to pieces. But, then, the satyagrahi
most resembles the member of a crazed cult or the mentally unhinged. True,
beholding such a sight might move the public to feel revulsion, but it is hard
to conceive how such a death will inspire respect for the victim.
Isn’t it the fact that a person who stands poised to
make the supreme sacrifice for an ideal also
and concurrently clings to life and, if not absolutely dreading death,
still loves life—and not just loves
life because it enables one to sacrifice it, which is how Gandhi conceived
life—isn’t it that fact that causes
the rest of humanity to honor martyrs and moves our consciences at their
untimely and unjust passing?
Gandhi so devalues life that life and death truly
become indistinguishable, and seeking to preserve life, let alone at the
ultimate price of self-immolation, becomes a contradiction in terms. Why sacrifice
one’s own life for the sake of others if it is, or should be, a matter of indifference
whether they are dead or alive?
It is also hard to fathom why Gandhi should feel
“exhilaration” at a satyagrahi’s
violent death or the smashing of his skull. To give one’s life for a just cause
is surely deserving of the highest respect but it merits such admiration
precisely because it is a sacrifice—because
life is so worth living and we all do, or should, want to live. Isn’t the
proper acknowledgment of such martyrdom not elation but awe at the human capacity to act out such devotion to an ideal as
well as mourning for a life that missed
out on the joy of living it to the
fullest? If pathos and poignancy attach to martyrdom, it can only be because of
the reverence we attach to life.
Beyond its shamefulness, Gandhi rejected nonviolence
born of weakness because it was politically ineffectual. If the votaries of
nonviolence abjured violence only from fear of retaliation, then the wrongdoer
had every right to dread what might ensue should they attain power and control
the levers of repression, and therefore had every incentive to resist unto the
death a handing over of power.
In order to convince the wrongdoer that one’s
nonviolence was not born of weakness, and hence that the wrongdoer had nothing
to fear if the tables were turned, satyagrahis
needed to demonstrate—make manifest—the willingness to forego violence even
when they did not fear violent
retaliation. One such scenario would be if those practicing nonviolence vastly
outnumbered and could easily overwhelm the wrongdoer, but chose not to.
The nonviolence of “India as a nation ... is that of
the weak,” Gandhi lamented. “If she were nonviolent in the consciousness of her
strength, Englishmen would lose their role of distrustf ul conquerors.... If
we, as Indians, could but for a moment visualize ourselves as a strong people
disdaining to strike, we should cease to fear Englishmen whether as soldiers,
traders or administrators, and they to distrust us.” (68) And again: “The
moment Englishmen feel that although they are in India in a hopeless minority,
their lives are protected against harm not because of the matchless weapons of
destruction which are at their disposal, but because Indians refuse to take the
lives even of those whom they may consider to be utterly in the wrong, that
moment will see a transformation in the English nation in its relation to
India.” (69)
Yet, real-life circumstances often preclude the
practical demonstration of a truly nonviolent spirit. How for example could the
skeletal inmates of a concentration camp, depleted of any capacity to resist,
let alone a capacity to overpower the wrongdoers, make manifest that, if roles
were reversed, they would not exact revenge? To be sure, it might be argued in
Gandhi’s defense that, if nonviolence is to work, it cannot suddenly be invoked
when a struggle has already passed the point of no return.
One might also notice in the passages just quoted
Gandhi’s naïve premise that the fundamental barrier dividing British and
Indians was psychological (“fear” and “distrust”) and not a material clash of
interests. On other occasions he speculated that the British opposed Indian
independence because of “the great ignorance that prevails in England about
India. Many of the best Englishmen believe that we are incapable of defending
ourselves or managing our Finance.” (70)
In practice, however, Gandhi harbored few illusions
that the antagonistic relationship and consequent British resort to force
sprang from brutal exploitation, while the British decision whether to stay or
leave would ultimately be decided, not by winning their trust, but by their
cold calculation of the bottom line.
3/QUICKENED CONSCIENCE
How does satyagraha
work?
Gandhi professed that satyagraha was not just nonviolent but also noncoercive. In
reality, his civil resistance campaigns combined varying degrees of abnegation
and coercion. (1)
At one pole was a tactic such as fasting, which
manifestly contained a large component of self-suffering, but which could also
be coercive. Gandhi’s defense of public-spirited fasts as purely noncoercive
does not convince.
Gandhi posited a distinction between selfless fasts
aimed at benefiting others (noncoercive) versus selfish fasts aimed at benefiting
one’s self (coercive). Some instances would appear to be fairly straightf
orward: a father who fasts to dissuade his son from snorting cocaine versus a
son who fasts to persuade his father to buy him a BMW.
But in real life it is not so simple. If the alleged
wrongdoer does not concur on the legitimacy of the faster’s goal, he will
surely experience the fast as
coercive even if the faster conceives it as a beneficent act.
When late in life Gandhi slept naked with young girls
to test his capacity for sexual restraint, many of his associates were appalled
to the point of breaking offrelations with him. Gandhi dubbed their severance
of ties a form of “noncooperation with me,” and was deeply troubled by the
loss. Nonetheless, he insisted that he had done no wrong, indeed, that his
religious faith compelled him along his chosen path. If they had gone one step
further and fasted in protest and to awaken his conscience, would theirs have
been a noncoercive or coercive act?
In the absence of a shared moral consensus between the
fasting “penitent” and the alleged wrongdoer, the fast will always be
subjectively felt by its target as coercive and—for all anyone knows and can
know—it also would be, on Gandhi’s own terms, objectively coercive. Who’s to
say, definitively, whether or not the faster’s goal is desirable?
Gandhi himself acknowledged that, however sincere,
the faster might be wrongly motivated and hence morally culpable, and also that
only a thin line might separate selfless from selfish goals. After his
imprisonment for protesting the salt tax Gandhi went on a fast because the
British denied him permission to see, and thereby also to provide aid and
comfort to, his ailing comrades. “The deprivation of touch with these
fellow-prisoners,” he pled, “is unbearable for me.” Was his a selfish or selfless
fast?
Gandhi declared that, if in his “ignorance” he might
“try through a fast to make the nation agree to an improper demand, I am sure
that the nation ought not to yield to such a demand merely for sparing my life,
no matter how much it is convinced of my services to it in the past.” Likewise,
he avowed, no doubt sincerely, that “my contemplated fast ... is in no way
intended to deflect anyone from what he believes is the course of duty for
him.” But isn’t it more likely that others would give ground, even if he was in
the wrong, because they wouldn’t want the Mahatma to suffer or die? Despite
himself, his fast would coerce.
In the hands of a revered but still flawed public figure,
the weapon of a fast can, in other words, easily lend itself to abuse. Gandhi’s
fallback defense that one must trust the judgment of an experienced satyagrahi such as himself scarcely
helped. The fact that he occasionally approved of fasts that, although
politically irreproachable, were nonetheless self-interested also muddied the
waters. Thus, he allowed that “under certain circumstances it is permissible to
fast for an increase in wages on behalf of one’s group,” and that “if, in spite
of the collections of food grains in the depot, the hungry cannot get it, ...
they can go on a fast unto death and thus secure relief for themselves and for
others.” What happened to his stricture that one must not personally benefit
from a fast?
Gandhi also purported that moving someone to act (or
not act) as the result of a public fast is no more coercive than someone being
moved to act (or not act) by the “love of Jesus” or the love of family and
friends. But in the face of sinful temptation, the private voice of one’s
conscience admonishing to “do the right thing,” is of a different quality from
the coercion of a public spectacle that, whatever the faster’s intention,
inevitably carries injury to the object of the fast. To act out of love for
Jesus registers the triumph of one’s moral faculty over less ennobling impulses,
whereas if one succumbs to the external pressure of a fast, it might just be
because of vanity and fear of earthly loss. Thus, when tempted by infidelity,
the “higher” voice of conscience curbs one’s carnal desires. But if a spouse in
the know decides to fast, it might quicken the would-be adulterer’s conscience,
or it might just quicken his embarrassment at being caught, and his dread of
being publicly humiliated and losing conjugal rights. (2)
If fasting stood at one pole of satyagraha, at the other extreme was what Gandhi called
“noncooperation” such as a general strike, which he in principle supported, (3)
although it obstructed society’s functioning. (4) Such a tactic was manifestly
coercive, yet insofar as the participant faced the loss of a paycheck, punitive
sanctions, even internment and death, noncooperation also entailed varying
degrees of self-suffering. (5)
To blunt its coercive edge, Gandhi stressed that even
noncooperation “must have its roots in love. Its object should not be to punish
the opponent or to inflict injury upon him.... we must make him feel that in us
he has a friend and we should try to reach his heart.” And again: “We do want
to paralyze the Government considered as a system—not, however, by
intimidation, but by the irresistible pressure of our innocence.” (6) He did
allow that, as a “practical” matter, even if noncooperation sprang from the
“nonviolence of the weak,” (7) i.e., not from love of the exploiters but from
fear that a violent assault on them would provoke yet more violent retribution,
it could still be effective “if a sufficient number of people practice it.” (8)
But Gandhi stubbornly refused to concede that, although love and innocence
might lower the temperature of a heated labor struggle, coercion remained the
overriding factor at play in noncooperation. (9)
Between the self-suffering of a fast and the coercive
force of a strike, Gandhi’s other tactics occupied a middle ground. He
advocated various forms of civil disobedience, such as nonpayment of taxes, that
contained equal parts coerciveness (depriving the state of needed revenues,
undermining the rule of law) and self-suffering (going to jail, paying punitive
fines), and various forms of civil resistance, the coerciveness of which ranged
from more (“political” boycotts targeting goods produced by another country) to
less (“unaggressive” picketing). (10)
Finally, it merits mentioning one potent if latent
form of violence lurking in the background of Gandhi’s activities, of which he
was fully cognizant and which he was not averse to exploiting. If the British
did not acquiesce in his nonviolent demands, then they would have to cope with
wholesale violent resistance instead. “I have claimed in private correspondence
with English friends,” Gandhi noted, “that it is because of my incessant
preaching of the gospel of nonviolence and my having successfully demonstrated
its practical utility that so far the forces of violence, which are undoubtedly
in existence ..., have remained under complete control.” (11) On the other
hand, there is no reason to doubt that Gandhi was sincere in his oft-stated
belief that the resort of Indians to violence and terrorism would ultimately
harm the cause of Indian independence. (12)
The essence of Gandhi’s creed was the transformative
power of pristine self-suffering. He believed that such suffering would put on
display the “human dignity” of the victim and thereby “quicken into life” the
public’s “sluggish conscience,” “awaken the life” of the “sleeping conscience,”
“quicken the dead conscience into life,” “make people think and act,” strike a
“sympathetic chord,” “stir us out of our complacency,” and “evoke by his truth
and love expressed through his suffering” the “inherent goodness of human
nature.”
“The world is touched by sacrifice,” Gandhi
proclaimed. “It can tame the wildest beast, certainly the wildest man,” it
compels “public opinion ... to desist from the hypocrisy which is eating into
them.” (13)
Once having aroused public opinion from its
listlessness, the satyagrahi would
then be well-placed to “mobilize” it “against the evil which he is out to
eradicate, by means of a wide and intensive agitation,” while his “success is
the certain result of suffering of the extremist character, voluntarily
undergone.” (14)
It is not clear, however, why suffering in and of
itself or, for that matter, allied with “love,” would galvanize the bystander,
let alone convert the alleged wrongdoer. Were the “pro-life” half of the
American population to converge on abortion clinics and pledge a collective
fast unto the death until and unless the clinics ceased performing abortions,
the “pro-choice” half would almost certainly not be converted by such a
spectacle.
In other words, it is not suffering alone that
touches but suffering in the pursuit of a
legitimate goal. The public’s recognition of the legitimacy of such a goal
presumes, however, a preexisting broad consensus, if only latent or incipient,
according to which the victims justly deserve what they seek.
When Gandhi referred to the victim’s “innocence,” (15)
it was in effect, although he didn’t always specify it, innocence in a double
sense: of means—while willing to endure pain, the victim refrains from inflicting
pain on others— and of ends—the
victim seeks a right that cannot in good conscience be denied because it
resonates with the “normal moral sense of the world.” (16) “I rely for
success,” Gandhi explained, “upon the inherent justice of the national cause
and the equally just means adopted for its vindication.” (17)
If the “weapon” of satyagraha “depends for success upon the gathering of public
opinion,” (18) then, the more incontrovertible the ends, the more self-suffering
as a means will spur “enlightened public opinion” into action. (19) But
inversely, self-suffering will not pierce the emotional armor of wrongdoers who
are convinced, either due to inimical interest or inimical ideology or, what’s
often the case, both conjoined, that the demands of the victim lack justice.
The spectacle of martyrdom might induce some degree of pity but, in and of
itself, it won’t induce those profiting from a system and convinced of its
justice to make major concessions.
Gandhi himself conceded that his interlocutors might
be as convinced in the rightness of their opinions as he was of his own (“I
realize what may appear to me prejudice may be enlightenment to others”), (20)
and that he had to be open to the possibility that his interlocutors might be
right and he himself wrong (“Nobody in this world possesses absolute truth.
This is God’s attribute alone. Relative truth is all we know”). (21) But why
then would or should the (alleged) wrongdoer be converted by the self-sacrifice
of those pursuing a goal, the justice of which is concededly dubious?
Unlike when violence is brought into play, Gandhi
rightly observed, if the goal turns out to be off the mark, the satyagrahi’s suffering will not have
caused bodily harm to the unfairly targeted wrongdoer: “He does not make others
suffer for his mistakes.” (22) But it is also a fact that the wrongdoer’s
hardened self-interest conveniently packaged in righteous ideology will almost
certainly stifle the voice of justice and trump the urgings of pity, thereby
nullifying the power of nonviolence.
The point I am making here finds vivid illustration
in this passage from Gandhi: “Our triumph consists in thousands being led to
the prisons like lambs to the slaughterhouse. If the lambs of the world had
been willingly led, they would have long ago saved themselves from the
butcher’s knife. Our triumph consists again in being imprisoned for no wrong
whatsoever. The greater our innocence,
the greater our strength and the swifter our victory.” (23)
If the injustice is morally assimilable, then self-suffering
can, and likely will, prick the conscience. But the potent brew of interest and
ideology can easily persuade that those being rounded up harbor criminal intent
and consequently deserve their fate. Did millions of innocent Jews being led to
the crematoria “like lambs to the slaughter-house” prick the Nazi conscience?
It might be said that they did not go smilingly and cheerfully—theirs was the
“nonviolence of the weak”—but if the Nazis could morally rationalize the
extermination of one million Jewish children—whose innocence of means and ends
could be purer?—it is probable that they would also have rationalized the
non-vindictive and voluntary self-immolation of the Jews.
To make sense of Gandhi’s doctrine of satyagraha or, at any rate, to extract
from it a rational core, a further distinction needs to be drawn between its differing
“theaters” of action and protagonists. On some occasions, such as when a member
in the intimacy of his ashram went astray, Gandhi pitched his fasts at, and
they were designed to reform, the actual wrongdoer. Their efficacy hinged on
the existence of moral and affective bonds between the wrongdoer and the
fasting “penitent.” The wrongdoer mends his or her ways because of both a
genuine epiphany of having erred and solicitude for the beloved suffering
penitent. (24)
On other occasions Gandhi pitched his fasts at, and
they were designed to galvanize, a sympathetic public. The success of such
self-suffering depended less on intimate bonds of affection, i.e., the “love”
of Gandhi’s person, than on a broad moral consensus, i.e., the manifest injustice
of the situation that prompted his fast. In this instance, the venue is not
private but public and concomitantly the target of the fast is not the
wrongdoer but the bystander.
The confusion sets in when Gandhi conflates reforming
a wrongdoer who is an intimate with reforming a bitter political opponent.
Where mutual love binds the penitent and the wrongdoer, the former’s self-suffering
might very well sober up the latter. A Jewish mother’s anguish has pulled many
a wayward son back onto the straight and narrow. But it strains credulity that
Gandhi’s penance could, as he alleged, “melt” Hitler’s heart.
Of course, the premise of Gandhi’s doctrine is that
feelings of love and a common humanity did bind Hitler and his victims. But
even if he is right, and even if, on the remote chance, they could have been
aroused from their slumber, is it at all plausible that these feelings would
have stayed Hitler’s demons? One would be hard-pressed to answer this question
in the affirmative. The efficacy of penitential self-suffering to reform a
wrongdoer diminishes the further removed the wrongdoer is. It might work with a
wayward family member or friend, but not with an anonymous fellow citizen or
some distant member of the human race. If the wrongdoer is also convinced that
he is in the right and stands to materially lose if he is shown to be in the
wrong, it is almost certain that self-suffering, however pure and intense, will
leave him cold.
In short, it defies belief that, if the groups
targeted by Hitler for extermination had practiced noncoercive, nonviolent
resistance, they could have quickened his conscience and melted his heart. The
only Gandhian strategies possibly effective against a Hitler would be
noncooperation on a mass scale, and mobilizing sympathetic public opinion
through self-suffering, in order, not to tug at his heartstrings, but to
politically defeat him.
The exceptions to this rule are more apparent than
real. True, Gandhi could direct a fast at a tyrannical British official whom he
only knew from afar and in a formal capacity, yet the official proved
responsive. If the official did relent, it was not, however, from a love of
Gandhi, or because Gandhi’s fast had fanned the embers of his conscience into
life, but almost certainly because Gandhi’s fast threatened to awaken the “dead
conscience” of a sympathetic public and thereby politically isolate him.
A fast unto the death by Gandhi could also move
anonymous millions of Hindus and Muslims to desist from intercommunal genocide.
It was not, however, an emotional attachment per se to Gandhi that restrained
them. Nor was it an awakened love of the “Other”—i.e., the mutual recognition
by Hindus and Muslims of their common humanity— and self-knowledge that
communal hatred was wrong.
If Indians ceased, momentarily, slaughtering each
other, it was because of the mutual intuition that, when all was said and done,
the Mahatma represented what was the highest and best in them, and had earned,
through a lifetime of selfless devotion to public service, a claim on their
obedience. It was a role that Gandhi had uniquely carved out for himself. Only
a fast initiated by Gandhi, and him alone, could have cooled fratricidal
hatreds whipped into a frenzy.
Self-suffering might move a loved one to mend his
ways. It might also awaken the conscience of a public otherwise passive in the
face of injustice. But as a rule it will not deter persons driven by righteous
fury and defending perceived interests. Only a Gandhi could possess such over
powering spiritual force; it lived and died with his person. This was his great
personal triumph, but also his great political failure. The tactic has no
generalized value.
4/PEOPLE’S MAN
What did satyagraha
look like in action?
I will examine Gandhi’s key political interventions
during the period 1930–1947, when his ideas were put to their severest tests.
Discrimination and
immorality. Gandhi launched his satyagraha
campaigns to reform Indian society on the premise that a real or latent
majority of Indians supported his social agenda. The point of each campaign was
not to create a constituency ex nihilo, but through self- suffering to quicken
the people’s conscience on the basis of an already existing or incipient
consensus. He aimed at “cultivating and ascertaining the opinion” of this preexisting
constituency, and thus bring to bear the “force of public opinion” by awakening
it from its slumber and “rous[ing]” it to a “sense of ... duty.” (1)
The target audience of Gandhi’s campaigns was not the
implacable opponents of reform but the actual or potential supporters of it,
whom he wanted to goad into action. “The impending fast is against those who
have faith in me,” he declared on one such occasion.
Therefore, it is not against the English official
world, but it is against those Englishmen and women who, in spite of the
contrary teaching of the official world, believe in me and the justice of the
cause I represent. Nor is it against those of my countrymen who have no faith
in me, whether they be Hindus or others; but it is against those countless
Indians ... who believe that I represent a just cause. Above all, it is
intended to sting the Hindu conscience into right religious action. (2)
And again: “What my penance should do is to quicken
the conscience of those who know me and believe in my bona fides” and who
“realized that [I] was their friend.” (3)
Thus, in undertaking to remove the “blot” of
untouchability by opening the doors of Hindu temples to the Harijans (“children of God”), (4) Gandhi
presumed that a majority of Hindus supported such a reform: “the public is
itself ready for it.” The purpose of satyagraha
was to coax the Hindu majority into acting on what it had already come to
regard as right: “My opinion is that the mind of the majority is for this
reform if it comes stealthily. Therefore, reformers should prepare the ground
now ceaselessly and vigilantly to convert the passive attitude towards the
reform into active approval thereof”; “The fast, if it has to come, will not be
for the coercion of those who are opponents of the reform, but it will be
intended to sting into action those who have been my comrades or who have taken
pledges for the removal of untouchability.... My fast, therefore, ought not to
affect the opponents of reform, nor even fellow-workers and the millions who
have led me to believe that they were with me and the Congress in the campaign
against untouchability, if the latter have on second thoughts come to the
conclusion that untouchability is not after all a crime against God and
humanity”; “The whole idea of my fast is based on the belief that a large
section of the people favor temple-entry, but they do not voice it.” (5)
In launching a campaign to rid India of the scourge
of alcoholism, Gandhi likewise banked on the belief that “public opinion” could
be consolidated around such a reform. (6) When challenged why he did not also
wage campaigns to rid India of other debasing indulgences such as gambling,
smoking and the cinema, Gandhi candidly responded: “The drink evil has been
recognized as such by the people of this land. But the other evils are more or
less fashionable”; “Smoking has attained alarming respectability. When a vice
reaches that state, it becomes difficult to eradicate”; “These vices were
fashionable and therefore were not capable of being dealt with like
prohibition. I claim to be a practical reformer. I know almost instinctively
what vices are ripe for being publicly dealt with.” (7)
In other words, no amount of self-suffering would
move the public to act against a vice that it did not already deplore. That
being the case, Gandhi refused to squander precious time on deviancies of which
the public did not already disapprove: “I would not discuss any matter which
does not seem to be of immediate importance and about which there is the
slightest room for doubt.” (8)
To be sure, Gandhi did also profess that self-suffering
would “finally break the wall of prejudice” of those violently opposed to his
social reforms: “the hardest heart and the grossest ignorance,” “the stoniest
heart of the stoniest fanatic.” (9) He also predicted that it would “melt the
hearts” of those profiting from vice. (10) But still, the thrust of his
campaigns was clearly to energize a latently sympathetic public via self-suffering,
and utilize this “force of public opprobrium” in order to democratically
overrule, or so cially isolate, or force the capitulation of, or reach a
principled compromise with, the diehards. (11)
Inequality and
exploitation. Gandhi cast himself as the voice of India’s impoverished
“dumb millions”: “I unhesitatingly say that I am a people’s man. Every moment
of my life I feel for the starving millions. I live and am prepared to lay down
my life to relieve their sufferings and mitigate their miseries.” When asked
why he did not use a “thick mattress” and always traveled third class on the
railway, Gandhi replied, “I do all I can to merge myself into the poor millions
of India.” (12)
Gandhi conceived swaraj as much more than political
independence, or what he dismissively dubbed the “mere transfer of power.” He
sought the “complete deliverance of the toiling yet starving millions from the
dreadful evil of economic serfdom” and “independence of the poorest and the
lowliest in the land.” “Unless poverty and unemployment are wiped out from
India,” he declared, “I would not agree that we have attained freedom.” (13)
Beyond India’s redemption Gandhi also aspired “to
deliver the so-called weaker races of the earth from the crushing heels of
Western exploitation in which England is the greatest partner.” He expressed
“hope” that the Indian struggle was “only part of the general struggle of
colonial peoples against world capitalism and imperialism and that India is the
vanguard in the world movement of colonial and agricultural masses for freedom,
economic and political.” (14)
By virtue of both his personal creed and India’s
crushing poverty, Gandhi adopted an austere code of what constituted just
remuneration in a well-ordered society: “A thing not originally stolen must
nevertheless be classified as stolen property if we possess it without needing
it”; “whoever appropriates more than the minimum that is really necessary for
him is guilty of theft”; “to live above the means befitting a poor country is
to live on stolen food”; “each man shall have the wherewithal to supply all his
natural needs and no more”; “The rich, moneyed man, who made his riches by
exploitation or other questionable means, was no less guilty of robbery than
the thief who picked a pocket or broke into a house and committed theft. Only
the former took refuge behind the façade of respectability and escaped the
penalty of law.” (15)
To eradicate violence and crime, according to Gandhi,
the “cruel inequality that obtains today” (16) must also be eliminated: “A
nonviolent system of government is clearly an impossibility so long as the wide
gulf between the rich and the hungry millions persists”; “No one has ever
suggested that grinding pauperism can lead to anything else than moral
degradation.” (17)
Nonetheless Gandhi rejected the traditional demand of
the Indian Left to forcibly expropriate large propertyholders and nationalize
the means of production. Instead he championed the “theory of trusteeship,”
according to which the owning class would be coaxed by nonviolent resistance to
utilize its “excess” wealth for society’s betterment: “I do not believe that
the capitalists and landlords are all exploiters by an inherent necessity or
that there is a basic or irreconcilable antagonism between their interests and
those of the masses.” (18)
Here is not the place to weigh the merits or demerits
of Gandhi’s trusteeship scheme. (19) I will also set aside the financial
dependence of Gandhi on the Indian capitalists whom he shielded from popular
wrath. (20) My concern is instead with the practicality of the means Gandhi
proposed to realize his trusteeship goal.
Occasionally Gandhi foretold that the sacrifice and
tenderness of their workers would convert property-owners from ruthless
exploiters into enlightened guardians of the nation’s patrimony. The rich would
come to realize after “kind” gestures that they should not “squander [their]
gains in luxurious or extravagant living, but must use them” for the poor: “I
want, by means of suffering, to awaken them to their sense of duty, I want to
melt their hearts and get them to render justice to their less fortunate
brethren. They are human beings and my appeal to them will not go in vain”; “If
we treat these rich people with decency, they would fulfill the expectations we
have of them”; “If we win their confidence and put them at their ease, we will find
that they are not averse to progressively sharing their riches with the
masses”; “We should struggle against them in the same way and for the same
reason, as lovingly and reluctantly and with as much respect and politeness as
we do against our blood-relations.” (21)
Just as Gandhi now and again suggested that the
British would consent to India’s independence if only their irrational fear and
distrust were assuaged, so he suggested that the wealthy might cease exploiting
the poor if only their “fear and distrust” could be assuaged. (22)
When pressed hard, however, Gandhi conceded that he
could not point to a single precedent for his belief that self-suffering and
love would convert greedy capitalists into philanthropic trustees, and that
consequently his modus operandi amounted to a giant leap of faith. (23) Indeed,
aren’t capitalists convinced—and they don’t lack in proofs of their own—that
the system is fair, rewarding the enterprising few and penalizing the slothful
many?
But Gandhi also exhorted the working class to
organize and mobilize—that is, to realize its latent power and coercive
force—if it wanted property-owners to distribute equitably their ill-gotten
gains: “Immediately the worker realizes his strength, he is in a position to
become a cosharer with the capitalist instead of remaining his slave”; “What
you must do is to demonstrate to the capitalists the power of labor and they
will consent to be the trustees of those who toil for them”; “What is necessary
is that laborers or workers should know their rights and should also know how
to assert them”; “When the workers are better organized and more self-sacrificing,
their power would grow. You are not conscious of your strength and therefore
you are oppressed”; “As soon as laborers are properly educated and organized
and they realize their strength, no amount of capital can subdue them.
Organized and enlightened labor can dictate its own terms”; “[C]apitalists were
after all few in number. The workers were many. But capital was well organized
and had learnt to combine. If labor realized its inherent strength and the
secret of combination it would rule capital instead of being ruled by it”;
“There is in the English language a very potent word—all languages have it:
‘No.’ And the secret is that when capital wants labor to say ‘Yes,’ labor roars
out ‘No.’ And immediately labor comes to recognize that it has the choice
before it of saying ‘No’ when it wants to say ‘No,’ it has nothing to fear and
it would not matter in the slightest degree that capital has guns and poison
gas at its disposal. Capital will still be perfectly helpless if labor will
assert its dignity making good its ‘No.’ Then labor does not need to retaliate,
but stands defiant receiving the bullets and poison gas and still insists upon
its ‘No’”; “The peasant, whether as a landless laborer or a laboring
proprietor, comes first. He is the son of the soil which rightly belongs or
should belong to him, not to the absentee landlord.... He has so to work as to
make it impossible for the landlord to exploit him. Closest cooperation amongst
the peasants is absolutely necessary.” (24)
If moral appeals did not persuade Indian
industrialists and landlords to “become guardians of the poor in the true sense
of the term and the latter are more and more crushed and die of hunger,” then
Gandhi advocated “nonviolent noncooperation and civil disobedience as the right
and infallible means.” (25) Indeed, he warned the haves that unless they gave
up their ill-gotten gains anarchy would ensue: “There is no other choice than
between voluntary surrender on the part of the capitalist of superfluities and
consequent acquisition of the real happiness of all, on the one hand, and on
the other, the impending chaos into which, if the capitalist does not wake up
betimes, awakened but ignorant, famishing millions will plunge the country and
which not even the armed force that a powerful Government can bring into play
can avert.” (26)
Still, Gandhi formally abjured “so-called classconflict,”
(27) counseling instead that “landlords and capitalists” be “persuaded and
converted,” (28) and often expressed disdain for worker strikes. (29) He could
be willfully blind to the glaring fact that his practical prescription for
abolishing exploitation and inequality ultimately relied not on the beneficence
of self-suffering but on the coercion of raw (if nonviolent) power. (30)
Aggression and occupation. In the course of World War II, Gandhi conjured
up sometimes complementary, PEOPLE’S MAN 67 sometimes contradictory scenarios
to defeat Axis aggression nonviolently. It appeared as if he were desperately
straining and improvising to prove the viability and relevance of satyagraha in the face of its ultimate
challenge.
Noncooperation.
Once the Axis powers realized that they could not exploit conquered territories
without the occupied population’s cooperation, Gandhi speculated, they would
withdraw: in the face of “quiet, dignified and nonviolent defiance,” the
“tyrant will not find it worth his while to go on with his terrorism,” and “he
would certainly have been obliged to retire.” Whatever Gandhi formally
preached, this tactic plainly made appeal not to the consciences or hearts of
the conquerors but to their balancesheets, i.e., material self-interest. (31)
In a variation of this scenario Gandhi concluded that noncooperation would not
result in mass slaughter because Hitler did not want to exploit the British
Empire but rather he sought to vanquish it—to get it to “admit defeat”—and,
consequently, if denied the adrenaline stimulus of a hunt, “he will lack the
zest to kill you. Every hunter has had this experience. No one has ever heard
of anyone hunting cows.” (32)
If the conquering power did not withdraw and committed
atrocities, Gandhi conjectured in the war’s early stages, the number of persons
killed would still be fewer if the captive population practiced nonviolent
resistance, while Europe as a whole would emerge from the bloodbath spiritually
redeemed:
Imagine the state of Europe today if the Czechs, the
Poles, the Norwegians, the French and the English had all said to Hitler: “You
need not make your scientific preparation for destruction. We will meet your
violence with nonviolence. You will therefore be able to destroy our nonviolent
army without tanks, battleships and airships.” It may be retorted that the only
difference would be that Hitler would have got without fighting what he has
gained after a bloody fight. Exactly. The history of Europe would then have
been written differently. Possession might (but only might) have been then
taken under nonviolent resistance, as it has been taken now after perpetration
of untold barbarities. Under nonviolence only those would have been killed who
had trained themselves to be killed, if need be, without killing anyone and
without bearing malice towards anybody. I daresay that in that case Europe
would have added several inches to its moral stature. And in the end I expect
it is the moral worth that will count. All else is dross. (33)
But if the conquering power did wipe out the
noncooperating captive population, such an outcome, according to Gandhi, would
still be preferable to violent resistance. Thus, “the Czechs may be annihilated
for disobedience to orders,” but “that would be a glorious victory for the
Czechs.” They would still have preserved intact their “soul, i.e., honor.” It
would also spell “the beginning of the fall of Germany” because—or so Gandhi
believed—aggressors might be able to massacre innocents one time but “an army
that dares to pass over corpses would not be able to repeat that experience.” (34)
He likewise counseled his own compatriots, “if the Führer attacked India” and
even if he mercilessly slaughtered Indians refusing to cooperate, still, “these
satyagrahis facing the army will go
down in history as heroes and heroines at least equal to those of whom we learn
in fables or cold history.” (35)
Self-suffering.
But what if the conquering power sought not the cooperation but instead the
displacement and dispossession of the captive population, or its outright
extermination? Keeping his faith in the efficacy of self-suffering and an
upwelling of love, Gandhi professed that nonviolent resistance could deter a
mad and murderous despot because “human nature in its essence is one and
therefore unfailingly responds to the advances of love.” (36)
In the face of skeptics and naysayers Gandhi
stubbornly rejoined:
As a believer
in nonviolence, I am not limiting its possibilities. Hitherto [Hitler] and his
likes have built upon their invariable experience that men yield to force.
Unarmed men, women and children offering nonviolent resistance without any bitterness
in them will be a novel experience for them. Who can dare say it is not in
their nature to respond to the higher and finer forces? They have the same soul
as I have.
If the Jews ...
adopt active nonviolence, i.e., fellow-feeling for the gentile Germans
deliberately, they cannot do any harm to the Germans and I am as certain as I
am dictating these lines that the stoniest German heart will melt.
Sufferings of
the nonviolent have been known to melt the stoniest hearts. I make bold to say
that if the Jews can summon to their aid the soul power that comes only from
nonviolence, Herr Hitler will bow before the courage which he has never yet
experienced.
I do not
despair of [Hitler] responding to human suffering even though caused by him.
But I must refuse to believe that the Germans as a nation have no heart or
markedly less than the other nations of the earth.
[The Axis
powers] belong to the same species as the so-called democracies or, better
still, war-resisters themselves. They show in their family circles the same
tenderness, affection, consideration and generosity that war-resisters are
likely to show even outside such circles. The difference is only of degree....
It is therefore a matter of rule of three to find out the exact amount of non
violence required to melt the harder hearts of the Fascists and the Nazis, if
it is assumed, as it is, the so-called democracies melt before a given amount
of nonviolence.
Even a Nero is
not devoid of a heart. The unexpected spectacle of endless rows upon rows of
men and women simply dying rather than surrender to the will of an aggressor
must ultimately melt him away and his soldiery.
Indeed it is
not quite inconceivable that the loving sacrifice of many may bring an insane
man to his senses. Instances are not wanting of absolutely insane people having
come back to their senses.
Nonviolent
action, if it is adequate, must influence Hitler and easily the duped Germans.
No man can be turned into a permanent machine.
I must adhere
to my faith in the possibility of the most debased human nature to respond to
nonviolence.... I will not belittle the power of nonviolence or distrust the
Führer’s capacity to respond to true nonviolence.
Some people say
that satyagraha is of no avail
against a person who has no moral sense. I join issue with that. The stoniest
heart must melt if we are true and have patience. I have met human monsters
from my early youth. I have found that even they are not beyond redemption if
we know how to touch the right chord in their soul. (37)
It is hard not to respect the resilience of Gandhi’s
faith. But it is also hard not to see the obvious flaws in it. If Hitler was
genuinely persuaded of the necessity of lebensraum (living space) and the malignity
of the Jews, and if expanding Germany’s borders and eliminating Jews and other
“defective” people served Germany’s interests (as he construed them), why
should suffering allied to love have converted him?
In fact, just as Gandhi conceded that noncooperation
in the face of the Axis invaders might result in mass, albeit redemptive,
death, so he was less than totally convinced of the efficacy of self-suffering,
at any rate in the here and now. Thus he also advised that, if the Nazis proved
implacable foes, Jews should go mutely to their deaths because such a dignified
sacrifice would be their ultimate salvation: “If the Jewish mind could be
prepared for voluntary suffering, even the massacre [of Jews by Hitler] ...
could be turned into a day of thanksgiving and joy that Jehovah had wrought
deliverance of the race even at the hands of the tyrant. For the God-fearing,
death has no terror. It is a joyful sleep to be followed by a waking that would
be all the more refreshing for the long sleep.” And again: “It is highly
probable that, as the writer says, ‘a Jewish Gandhi in Germany, should one
arise, could function for about five minutes and would be promptly taken to the
guillotine.’ But that will not disprove my case or shake my belief in the efficacy
of ahimsa. I can conceive the necessity of the immolation of hundreds, if not
thousands, to appease the hunger of dictators who have not believed in ahimsa....
Sufferers need not see the result during their lifetime. They must have faith
that if their cult survives, the result is a certainty.” (38)
Gandhi and the Nazi
Holocaust
Gandhi has been harshly criticized for counseling
martyrdom to European Jewry during the Nazi holocaust. But he also repeatedly
and with uncharacteristic fervor denounced the murderous Nazi assault. “The
German persecution of the Jews,” he declared, “seems to have no parallel in
history. The tyrants of old never went so mad as Hitler seems to have gone....
If there ever could be a justifiable war in the name of and for humanity, a war
against Germany, to prevent the wanton persecution of a whole race, would be
completely justified.” (39)
Gandhi also retrospectively advised willful
selfimmolation to the Japanese victims of the atomic bomb. They should have
“come out in the open and let the pilot see that [they] have not a trace of
illwill against him.... If those thousands who were done to death in Hiroshima ...
had died with that prayerful action—died openly with that prayer in their
hearts—their sacrifice would not have gone in vain.” (40) And, as already
shown, Gandhi recommended martyrdom to the Czech nation and other actual and
potential victims of Axis aggression.
During the fratricidal bloodletting at the time of
India’s partition, Gandhi proclaimed, “I do not mind if each and every one of
the 500 [Hindu] families in your area [of East Bengal] is done to death [by
Muslims],” and “if all the [Hindu] Punjabis were to die to the last man without
killing, the Punjab would become immortal.” He also willed the death of all
Kashmiris, including the children—“everybody,
young and old, should die there valiantly”—to prevent the province’s
dismemberment by foreign marauders. (41)
In short, Gandhi’s pronouncements on the Nazi
holocaust might have been callous, but they also had the merit, albeit a
dubious one, of consistency.
If the goal of satyagraha
was to melt Hitler’s heart in the promise of earthly deliverance, yet it produces no results during the
terrestrial life of the sufferers, then it must be reckoned a political failure. Put otherwise, if all
Gandhi had to offer his disciples was posthumous redemption, it is unlikely
that the political movement he led would have had broad reach. The expectation
of earthly reward was implicit in his political message. Otherwise, why did he
call himself a “practical reformer”
and a “practical idealist”?
It is of course the nature of politics to carry in it
a high probability of defeat, and a meaningful political victory almost always
comes after many setbacks and lives lost. But it goes against the grain of the
political vocation to counsel a tactic that, however exalting, has no prospect
of success in the here and now—and melting Hitler’s heart through self-suffering
would appear to fall squarely in the “no prospect” column. Of course, it might
be argued that, whatever European Jewry did, its fate was sealed and, in the
face of certain death, nonviolent resistance would have been the most
redemptive form of martyrdom. (42) That, however, is a matter altogether
separate and apart from the question of whether self-suffering is a viable
tactic against a fanatical enemy. The answer to this question must be an
emphatic, if regrettable, “no.”
What held for Hitler also held for Gandhi’s nemesis
in the epic struggle for Indian independence. Winston Churchill was hardly
persuaded by Indian suffering to dismantle the British Empire. (43) The
interest-cum-ideology of Westminster easily trumped the suffering-cum-love of
the Indian downtrodden.
Gandhi himself harbored few illusions about what
dictated official British policy: “It is the material benefits which England
derives from the connection [with India] that matter to the British public. It
is the extinction of those benefits that matters most to the Indian masses who
can no longer bear the crushing burden”; “The Government, instead of telling
us, show by their many unmistakable acts that they will do anything but
sacrifice the material interest of their principals, the British manufacturers
and the like, who live on India’s exploitation”; “The British troops are in
India not to protect India but to protect British interests which were imposed
on India and which are now so well entrenched that even the British Government
cannot dislodge them. The British did not come here as philanthropists, nor is
there any altruism in their continued stay here.” (44)
“The English Ministers are pursuing what they believe
to be an honest policy,” Gandhi further noted. “It is their honest belief that
British rule in India has been, on the whole, for her good. They honestly
believe that under it India has advanced.” (45)
If British policy was dictated by material interest;
and if the British “will do anything but sacrifice the material interest”; and
if ideology effectively rationalized this self-interested policy, making it
appear not just benign but beneficial to Indians: then, should it surprise
that— contrary to Gandhi’s starry-eyed expectations—the martyrdom of Indians
failed to touch British imperialists, or that it failed to get “British
commerce with India ... purified of greed” and thereby put on “terms of mutual
help and ... equally suited to both”? (46)
Although Gandhi spoke of wanting to “convert the
administrators of the system,” he nonetheless qualified, “the conversion may or
may not be willing.” (47) And again: “to convert them or, if you will, even to
drive them out of the country.” (48) By the same token, although Gandhi spoke
of wanting to “wake up public conscience as also that of the authority,” he
nonetheless qualified, “assuming that the latter can have any conscience at
all.” (49) These caveats suggest that Gandhi intended to rely on more than
love-power to wrest independence from Great Britain.
In fact Gandhi conceived the struggle against British
imperialism in terms of making India ungovernable, and consequently unprofitable.
His modus operandi combined nonviolence, which neutralized British bayonets by
making British resort to them politically untenable; economic boycott, which
targeted British exports to India; and noncooperation, which nullified British
authority by flouting it.
Thus, far from trying to melt the hearts of British officialdom,
he foretold and forewarned: “In case India’s demand [for independence] is not
granted, there is bound to be a fierce boycott, and all the attention of Great
Britain will have to be absorbed in looking after her quickly-perishing trade
interests in India”; “If, notwithstanding their desire to the contrary, they
saw that their guns and everything they had created for the consolidation of
their authority were useless because of our non-use of them, they could not do
otherwise than bow to the inevitable and either retire from the scene, or
remain on our terms, i.e., as friends to coop erate with us, not as rulers to
impose their will upon us”; “Whether we convert them or not, we are determined
to make their rule impossible by nonviolent noncooperation.” (50)
On many an occasion Gandhi repudiated the use of
force to attain independence: “It is my confirmed belief that if India adheres
to the path of peace till the very end, the hearts of the most callous British officers
are bound to undergo a change”; “By self-suffering I seek to convert [the
Englishman], never to destroy him.” But truth be told, he did not seek to
spiritually convert the wrong-doing British imperialists. Instead, he set out
to coerce them, albeit nonviolently, into submission.
Gandhi endeavored to harness the latent power of the
Indian people in a tit-for-tat confrontation with the British Empire. His
actual means, as he admitted in moments of candor, had to be “force of will”
and “matching forces,” because “the chief obstacle in the way of swaraj” was
“the unwillingness of the British officials to part with power.” (51) And
again: “This much is certain, that argument is not what will carry conviction.
The British conviction will be in exact proportion to the strength we have
developed.” And yet again: “How can this British mentality be changed or, in
other words, how can power be wrested from such unwilling hands? No argument
will carry conviction to these statesmen; they are all seasoned hard-headed
soldiers. They like and appreciate facts, deeds. They will understand an open rebellion.” (52)
But Gandhi also held out the hope of reaching the
British “nation,” i.e., “public opinion,” through self-suffering: “I have
deliberately used the word ‘conversion.’ For my ambition is no less than to
convert the British people through nonviolence, and thus make them see the
wrong they have done to India.” (53) The British imperialists might have to be
driven out, but the conscience of the British people might yet be pricked.
Indeed, British public opinion could serve as a critical weapon for coercing
dyed-in-the-wool British imperialists to leave India.
Additionally, Gandhi counted on the international
community to stay the hand of British imperialism. “The British Government,
powerful though it is,” he observed during the Salt March, “is sensitive to
world opinion which will not tolerate repression of extreme political agitation
which civil disobedience undoubtedly is, so long as disobedience remains civil
and, therefore, necessarily nonviolent.” (54)
In his final reckoning Gandhi acknowledged that, if
the British finally decided to pack up and leave, it was not because Indians
had tugged at their heartstrings but because they had upended the exchequer’s
balance-sheet: “The British are bound to quit this country. They are a nation
of businessmen. They calculate the profit and loss from every transaction. They
have realized that it is no longer profitable to rule India”; “I know the
English better than anyone else. They are leaving India because they know that
they can derive no economic gain from continuing their rule in India and they
have realized that politically they can no longer keep us in subjection.” (55)
It was not the power of love but the juggernaut of
power that cleared the path to India’s independence.
CONCLUSION
A wave of popular revolts is now sweeping the planet.
In many instances, it was an act of nonviolent civil
resistance that either sparked the local uprising or marked its turning-point.
In Tunisia, it was the self-immolation of a street
vendor. In Cairo, it was the assault by goons on camelback against nonviolent
protesters in Tahrir Square. In New York City, it was the voluntary mass arrest
of demonstrators on the Brooklyn Bridge.
These actions “quickened” the public conscience.
People who had stood by indifferently and passively for decades suddenly came
to life.
The acts of nonviolent resistance resonated with a
broad public because of an already existing consensus that the system was
unjust.
In spirit and form, the epic events of the past year
appear like a page out of Gandhi’s life.
But it is also easy to see the limitations of
Gandhi’s teachings.
Neither Ben-Ali of Tunisia nor Mubarak of Egypt was
“melted” by the people’s self-suffering. They had to be forced from power. Neither the liberal mayor of Oakland nor the
liberal mayor of New York let their bleeding hearts prevent them from brutally
clearing out the “Occupy” movement.
Self-suffering might sting the conscience of the 99
percent and get them to act. But only the concerted and courageous power of the
overwhelming majority will get the 1 percent to budge and be gone.
The only language that the 1 percent understand, as
Gandhi conceded in his more candid moments, is “open rebellion.”
Still, Gandhi had a point. However costly the price
in lives of nonviolent resistance, it is probably still less than the price of
violent rebellion, while a nonviolent struggle augurs better for the future
than an armed struggle.
Once armed foreign forces entered Libya in “support”
of the popular revolt, the number of deaths skyrocketed. The probable order of
magnitude is manyfold greater than the total deaths in any of the other revolts
convulsing the Arab world. The result of the armed victory in Libya is a power
once again in thrall to external forces and likely to make most Libyans soon
yearn for a return to the days of Qaddafi. (1)
“Violence may destroy one or more bad rulers, but,”
Gandhi warned, “others will pop up in their places.”
The unspoken prejudice against nonviolence is that it
is cowardly and unmanly. But nonviolence as Gandhi conceived it can hardly be
dismissed on these counts. It takes an awful lot of bravery to march unarmed
into the line of fire “smilingly” and “cheerfully,” and get oneself blown to
pieces.
In his last days and amidst inter-communal slaughter,
Gandhi insisted on opening his prayer services in Hindu temples with a verse
from the Koran. It enraged Hindu fanatics to the point that one of them finally
murdered him.
Who would be so bold as to deny that Gandhi’s was a
heroic death?
If a criticism is to be leveled against Gandhi’s
nonviolence, it is that he sets the bar of courage too high for most mortals to
vault.
It is a central conceit of Gandhi’s doctrine that
nonviolent resistance in the face of evil is not only more ethical than
violence but could also achieve the same results.
The jury is still out on this.
It is certainly doubtful, as Arundhati Roy has
pointed out, that nonviolent resistance can achieve any results against a
ferocious enemy acting outside the glare of public scrutiny.
But what can be said with confidence is that the
results of violent resistance have been at best mixed.
The day after, bloody revolutions seem always to
disappoint, and in the scramble to the top, those with the most blood on their
hands seem always to get there first.
The challenge for the younger generation as it
embarks on the struggle to remake the world is to see how far it can advance without
having to use violence.
The further along it gets nonviolently, the more
likely it is that the new world will also be a better one.
NOTES
CHAPTER ONE
1. For the origin and meaning of the term satyagraha, see Stanley Wolpert, Gandhi’s Passion: The life and legacy of
Mahatma Gandhi (Oxford: 2001), p. 66.
2. I will be citing from The Collected Works of Mahatma Gandhi published
by the Ministry of Information and Broadcasting, Government of India. Hereafter:
CW.
3. I will be citing from
Mahatma Gandhi, The Essential Writings,
edited with an introduction and notes by Judith M. Brown (Oxford: 2008). Hereafter:
EW. I will also be citing from M. K. Gandhi, Non-violent Resistance (Satyagraha)
(Mineola, NY: 2001). Hereafter: NR.
4. CW, v. 70, p. 203. In the opinion of famed French
novelist Romain Rolland, who was also Gandhi’s biographer, however: “His mind
proceeds through successive experiments into action and he follows a straight
line, but he never stops, and one would risk error in attempting to judge him by
what he said ten years ago, because his thought is in constant evolution” (CW,
v. 48, p. 499).
5. CW, v. 69, pp. 291-92, CW, v. 73, pp. 276-77.
6. CW, v. 71, pp. 315-16, CW, v. 80, p. 222, CW, v.
82, p. 162.
7. I will be citing from M.
K. Gandhi, Hind Swaraj and Other Writings, edited by Anthony J. Parel
(Cambridge: 1997). Hereafter: HS.
8. CW, v. 42, p. 125, CW, v. 45, pp. 332-33, CW, v.
70, p. 242, CW, v. 80, p. 325, CW, v. 81, p. 319, CW, v. 82, p. 350.
9. CW, v. 67, p. 284.
10. CW, v. 42, p. 469, CW, v. 43, p. 307, CW, v. 46,
p. 6 (“Charges,” “apparent”), CW, v. 47, p. 378. In his most lucid, candid and,
as it were, consistent statement, Gandhi wrote: An apparent inconsistency
either in my life or in the affairs of the Ashram can be explained. There is
only an appearance of inconsistency in the action of a person who wraps up his
body in winter and keeps it uncovered in summer. He obeys the same principle
both when he covers the body and when he leaves it uncovered. Many such seeming
inconsistencies can be properly explained. Other inconsistencies are such in
fact. They are due to my or [the] Ashram’s weaknesses. They should be regarded
as moral deficiencies and every effort should be made to overcome them. Which
inconsistencies are really such and which are only apparent ones can be decided
only when we examine all of them one by one. (CW, v. 49, pp. 66-67)
11. CW, v. 66, p. 438 (“deviate”), CW, v. 74, p. 330
(“entirety”), CW, v. 78, p. 37 (“pure”), CW, v. 86, p. 315.
12. Gandhi tried convincing British authorities
during the Zulu War to arm his Indian volunteers but they refused.
13. On the last point, see Wolpert, Gandhi’s Passion, p. 97.
14. CW, v. 66, p. 438 (“army”), CW, v. 67, p. 285.
15. CW, v. 89, pp. 432-33.
16. CW, v. 42, p. 437, CW, v. 68, p. 269, NR, p. 132;
but see also Wolpert, Gandhi’s Passion,
p. 137.
17. CW, v. 63, pp. 373-74, CW, v. 72, pp. 30-31.
18. “Wybergh to Gandhi,” 3 May 1910, reproduced in
HS, pp. 139-40.
19. CW, v. 45, pp. 365-66.
20. HS, pp. 62-65.
21. CW, v. 44, p. 7.
22. CW, v. 55, p. 411 (“examination”), CW, v. 89, p.
295 (“prompting”). Here, the contradiction is perhaps less acute than meets the
eye: insofar as, according to Gandhi, “God alone knows the intentions” (CW, v.
72, p. 433, CW, v. 89, p. 295), in effect a man could only be judged by his
action. In still another permutation Gandhi asserted that “if the motive and
the action are pure, the doer is not responsible for the manifold consequences
that may arise from it” (CW, v. 45, p. 230).
23. CW, v. 53, p. 216, CW, v. 54, p. 416, CW, v. 67,
p. 284 (“pickets”), CW, v. 68, pp. 457-59.
24. CW, v. 71, p. 205.
25. CW, v. 68, pp. 81-82 (“classical”), CW, v. 86,
pp. 397-98.
26. CW, v. 71, p. 225 (“world”), CW, v. 75, p. 339.
27. CW, v. 70, pp. 204 (“sympathies”), 237, CW, v. 75,
p. 272, CW, v. 76, pp. 400-1 (“difference,” “resolving”), CW, v. 80, p. 294
(“creed”). Gandhi also supported the Allies because allegedly they were victims
of Axis aggression fighting defensive wars (CW, v. 71, pp. 10-11, CW, v. 72, p.
377).
28. CW, v. 69, p. 122, CW, v. 72, p. 60, CW, v. 73,
pp. 72, 85, 254, CW, v. 74, pp. 17, 27 (“enslaving”), 115, CW, v. 75, pp. 10
(“Churchillism”), 37, 45, 72, 205, CW, v. 84, p. 394. In an especially harsh
statement bracketing the Allies with the Axis, Gandhi wrote:
What is a war criminal? Was not war itself a crime
against God and humanity and, therefore, were not all those who sanctioned,
engineered, and conducted wars, war criminals? War criminals are not confined
to the Axis Powers alone. Roosevelt and Churchill are no less war criminals
than Hitler and Mussolini. Hitler was “Great Britain’s sin.” Hitler is only an
answer to British imperialism, and this I say in spite of the fact that I hate
Hitlerism and its anti- Semitism. England, America and Russia have all of them
got their hands dyed more or less red—not merely Germany and Japan. The
Japanese have only proved themselves to be apt pupils of the West. They have
learnt at the feet of the West and beaten it at its own game. (CW, v. 79, pp.
422-23)
29. CW, v. 59, p. 45 (“evil”), CW, v. 72, p. 187
(“mockery”).
30. CW, v. 68, pp. 137-41, 205, CW, v. 69, p. 290,
CW, v. 72, p. 230. I return to this point below.
31. CW, v. 70, p. 224, CW, v. 73, p. 208
(“essentially”), CW, v. 79, p. 424 (“logic”), CW, v. 83, p. 180 (“academic”),
CW, v. 86, p. 200 (“idealist”). Gandhi consciously pitched his language,
notable for its simplicity and accessibility, “with the general public in view,
and not ... men of learning” (CW, v. 45, p. 2).
32. He was also more likely to capitulate to an
interlocutor if faced with a moral plea rather than a reasoned argument;
attached limited value to reason in and of itself as a persuasive force; and
believed that “reason, as a rule, follows in the footsteps of feeling” (CW, v.
45, p. 244, CW, v. 48, p. 369, CW, v. 90, p. 216).
33. CW, v. 78, p. 16.
34. CW, v. 47, p. 253, CW, v. 79, p. 424 (“sacrifice”),
CW, v. 85, p. 368.
35. CW, v. 49, pp. 80-81; but cf. CW, v. 44, p. 357,
where he enters the qualification: “We cannot always live up to an ideal and sometimes
in actual practice we have to compromise it in order that we may not be forced
to give it up altogether.”
36. CW, v. 71, p. 257. But he could also be cautious
in his political judgments, as when he replied to a query on Bolshevik rule in
Russia, “It is perhaps somewhat shameful that I have to confess to you that I
do not yet know exactly what Bolshevism is for the simple reason that I have
not had time to study the inner working of the Russian revolution” (CW, v. 46,
p. 295). Later, while imprisoned during World War II, Gandhi read extensively
on socialist and communist doctrine, including Marx’s Capital (CW, v. 78, p. 69, CW, v. 82, p. 335). He was much better
read than he generally let on. The image he projected of an intellectual
simpleton, however ingenuous, should be taken with a grain of salt. For the
breadth and depth of his reading, see CW, v. 49, pp. 76-77, CW, v. 50, p. 310;
but cf. CW, v. 50, pp. 361-62, for Gandhi’s confessed ignorance of some of the
Western classics.
37. CW, v. 45, p. 7; cf. CW, v. 88, p. 17, where he
expresses disdain for “cinemas and theaters,” although he had been to “the
theater only once, when I was a small child,” and CW, v. 90, p. 340, where he
counsels that in newly independent India “there should be no place for cinema.”
38. CW, v. 43, pp. 336-38, CW, v. 74, pp. 114-16,
132, CW, v. 83, p. 333.
39. CW, v. 44, p. 18.
40. CW, v. 43, p. 321 (“heart”), CW, v. 47, p. 399,
CW, v. 73, p. 407 (“sustains”), CW, v. 81, p. 244 (“question”), CW, v. 82, p.
368, CW, v. 83, p. 258 (“root”); but cf. CW, v. 86, p. 338.
41. CW, v. 48, p. 412 (“real”), CW, v. 69, pp.
226-27; but cf. CW, v. 78, p. 8, CW, v. 79, p. 39, CW, v. 80, p. 238, CW, v.
86, p. 429, where Gandhi allows, “You may call yourself an atheist, but so long
as you feel akin with mankind you accept God in practice,” and also
contradictorily states regarding communists, “I dislike the idea of excluding
anybody because of his label,” and “I have no difficulty in working side by
side with communists.”
42. CW, v. 42, p. 422, CW, v. 43, p. 32, CW, v. 45,
p. 213 (“guided”), CW, v. 47, p. 292, CW, v. 49, p. 482 (“depend”), CW, v. 51,
pp. 70, 114, 222, 341, CW, v. 71, p. 306, CW, v. 73, pp. 91, 156, CW, v. 78,
pp. 259, 293. But cf. CW, v. 43, p. 32, CW, v. 74, p. 279, CW, v. 85, p. 17,
where Gandhi somewhat qualifies, “It has been my experience, with regard to
myself and many others, that after one has heard the inner voice, one finds
arguments in support of it”; “Many of my activities are undertaken in good
faith or intuitively. But they are not conducted on the basis of inspiration
alone; I have tried to place my convictions on a sound scientific foundation
while propagating them”; “I myself have not followed my instinct unless my
reason backed it ... before the fast began, my reason was able to back up my
instinct.” It should further be noted that he was not oblivious to political
realities on the ground when faith summoned him to act; rather the contrary
(CW, v. 71, p. 338). For the meaning Gandhi attached to his “inner voice,” cf.
CW, v. 50, p. 326.
43. CW, v. 51, p. 64.
44. CW, v. 74, p. 2; but cf. CW, v. 83, p. 180, and
NR, p. 109, where Gandhi makes modest claims for satyagraha as a “science.” The “laws” he derived from his science
were no less murky— e.g., “the law of civil resistance [is that] it is never
needed to be applied perpetually to a cause. Its sovereign efficacy lies in the
fact that it secures redress within a measurable though previously
unascertainable period” (CW, v. 47, p. 252). Incidentally, Gandhi contradicted this
“law” of civil resistance during World War II when he conceded that it might
not be efficacious against the Nazis and the satyagrahis would en masse have
to accept martyrdom without earthly redemption (see below).
45. CW, v. 42, p. 423, CW, v. 61, p. 113, CW, v. 72,
p. 230, CW, v. 86, pp. 155, 183, 262-63, 368, CW, v. 89, p. 121 (“votary”), NR,
pp. 286-87; but cf. CW, v. 73, p. 175.
46. CW, v. 72, p. 307; see CW, v. 62, p. 29, for his
“five simple axioms of nonviolence,” and CW, v. 63, p. 262, for his enumeration
“without argument” of the “implications and conditions of success of
nonviolence.”
47. CW, v. 45, p. 127 (“independent,” “essence”), CW,
v. 49, p. 38 (“certainly”), CW, v. 80, p. 306 (“everybody”), CW, v. 88, p. 160
(“blindly”).
48. CW, v. 71, pp. 103-4 (“authority,”
“experienced”), CW, v. 73, p. 31 (“author”).
49. CW, v. 47, p. 372 (“within”), CW, v. 73, p. 53
(“confident”).
50. CW, v. 48, p. 156 (“superficial,” “books”), CW,
v. 88, p. 1; but cf. CW, v. 53, p. 216, CW, v. 88, p. 325, where Gandhi avows,
“I claim no monopoly of the knowledge of the doctrine of satyagraha, it is open to anyone to give what meaning he likes to satyagraha and lay down rules also
according to his liking”; “It is not, however, claimed that all the laws of satyagraha have already been formulated.
I cannot say either that I myself know all the laws.”
51. CW, v. 78, p. 69.
52. CW, v. 43, p. 381, CW, v. 44, p. 47, CW, v. 51,
pp. 53, 64, CW, v. 81, p. 212 (“rule”), CW, v. 82, pp. 141-42 (“restrictions”),
CW, v. 83, p. 401 (“embarking”), CW, v. 88, p. 168 (“shastra”), CW, v. 90, pp.
377, 461.
53. CW, v. 78, p. 234.
54. CW, v. 71, p. 258 (“destroyed”), CW, v. 79, pp.
187, 382, CW, v. 89, p. 396.
55. CW, v. 44, p. 170 (pencil), CW, v. 49, pp. 167
(conversing), 200 (conversing), CW, v. 73, p. 444 (“jokes,” “pleasantries”),
CW, v. 79, pp. 68 (wristwatches), 292 (underwear), CW, v. 81, p. 192 (pencil),
CW, v. 90, p. 354 (he favored a reed pen).
56. A bit of the Big Brother also lurked in Gandhi.
He agreed that members of his ashram should keep “a personal diary of their
work, thoughts and ideas ..., and place them before [him] for his perusal so
that he could know the mind and work of each and every Ashramite, and make
necessary suggestions” (CW, v. 42, pp. 283-84, CW, v. 73, p. 416n1, CW, v. 74,
pp. 291-92, CW, v. 79, p. 380).
57. CW, v. 43, p. 32, CW, v. 45, p. 135, CW, v. 66,
p. 105, CW, v. 68, p. 59 (“handful”), CW, v. 72, pp. 378-81, 450, CW, v. 73,
pp. 388, 427, CW, v. 75, pp. 137, 146-66, CW, v. 78, pp. 64, 78, 218- 19, CW,
v. 81, pp. 87-89, EW, p. 15. For the meaning Gandhi attached to purna swaraj, and the distinction he
made out between it and “independence,” cf. CW, v. 45, pp. 263-64.
58. CW, v. 67, p. 123.
CHAPTER TWO
1. CW, v. 67, p. 437 (“thought”), CW, v. 68, p. 45
(“incapable”). For Gandhi’s expansive notion of nonviolence as well as the
practical exceptions he makes for it, see CW, v. 50, pp. 205-8.
2. CW, v. 68, pp. 29 (“universe”), 189
(“unadulterated”), CW, v. 69, p. 70 (“goodness”). Gandhi did not extend the
ambit of his doctrine of nonviolence to include “sub-human species,” on the
pragmatic grounds that his was not a religious program but a political one
designed to convert a broad constituency, although he himself “would not kill
insects, scorpions or even snakes. Nor should I under any circumstances take
meat” (CW, v. 61, p. 95, CW, v. 72, pp. 454-55, CW, v. 73, p. 385).
3. HS, p. 90.
4. CW, v. 48, p. 224 (“persists”), CW, v. 50, p. 207,
CW, v. 71, p. 408 (“extinct”), CW, v. 90, p. 195 (“destructive”).
5. CW, v. 67, pp. 436-37 (“clans,” “humankind,”
“family”), EW, pp. 324-26, NR, p. 179.
6. CW, v. 68, pp. 46 (“hell”), 204.
7. CW, v. 73, pp. 253-55. The British suppressed
publication of what Gandhi continued to believe was a “good letter” (CW, v. 73,
p. 288).
8. CW, v. 69, p. 69, CW, v. 72, p. 456, CW, v. 75, p.
60, CW, v. 78, p. 225, EW, p. 335, NR, pp. 32, 72, 149. Gandhi seemed however
to consider the “shaming” of a wrongdoer legitimate (EW, pp. 206, 336, CW, v.
83, p. 268).
9. CW, v. 71, p. 403, NR, pp. 182, 185-86.
10. CW, v. 69, p. 73 (“potent”), HS, p. 146.
11. CW, v. 69, p. 69.
12. CW, v. 43, pp. 93, 338. 13. CW, v. 43, p. 339.
14. CW, v. 71, p. 225. 15. CW, v. 66, p. 421, EW, p. 56 (“distinguishes”).
16. CW, v. 43, p. 133, CW, v. 45, p. 360, CW, v. 59,
p. 42 (“pop”), CW, v. 72, pp. 136, 217 (“blind”), HS, pp. 77-78 (esp. footnotes
151, 152), 81 (“seed”). 17. CW, v. 45, p. 249. 18. CW, v. 45, p. 349.
19. CW, v. 46, pp. 1-3, 29-31, CW, v. 48, p. 338
(“worst”). 20. CW, v. 72, pp. 214 (“deliverance”), 229, CW, v. 73, pp. 26-27
(“superior”), 324, CW, v. 75, p. 441 (“stronger”).
21. CW, v. 72, p. 214. Towards the end of World War
II Gandhi seemed to qualify this prognostication with the caveat that only if
India were not freed would the Allies’ victory inevitably wreak future horrors
(CW, v. 79, pp. 131-32).
22. CW, v. 86, pp. 116 (“out-Hitlering”), 247-48
(“super-Hitlerism”), 436 (“crushed”).
23. CW, v. 75, p. 441. For a variation of this
argument in the instance of a rapist’s assault, see CW, v. 68, pp. 81-82.
24. CW, v. 72, p. 229.
25. I will only consider here Gandhi’s differentiated
approach to violence against other human beings. For Gandhi’s dissent from the
sanctity Jainism attaches to all nonhuman life, because “in life it is
impossible to eschew violence completely,” cf. CW, v. 84, pp. 230-32, 391-92.
26. CW, v. 51, pp. 18-19, 24-25 (in this last passage
Gandhi enters the additional caveat that for such resistance to be truly
nonviolent, “One’s aim should not be to inflict pain nor should pain be the
result”), CW, v. 72, pp. 387-88, 434, CW, v. 74, p. 368, CW, v. 89, p. 481.
27. CW, v. 68, p. 57. However, according to Gandhi,
once having adopted the creed of nonviolence, one forswore the option of
violent retaliation (CW, v. 74, pp. 64, 75, but cf. CW, v. 74, pp. 297-98,
which seems to contradict this).
28. CW, v. 71, pp. 224-25.
29. CW, v. 68, pp. 137-38 (“canons”). Gandhi
similarly defended Chinese armed resistance to Japanese aggression (CW, v. 68,
p. 203).
30. CW, v. 68, pp. 137-38; cf. CW, v. 48, p. 106,
“Zionism meaning reoccupation of Palestine has no attraction for me.”
31. CW, v. 84, pp. 440-41.
32. See for example Simone Panter-Brick, Gandhi and the Middle East: Jews, Arabs and imperial interests (London: 2008).
33. CW, v. 87, p. 134 (“punishment”), CW, v. 89, pp.
242-43 (“traitors”).
34. His occasionally nonjudgmental attitude also
deserves notice. Thus he replied to a questioner:
If like many others, nonviolence does not appeal to
your heart, you should discard it. I shall not find fault with you for that,
and, if others do, you should not care. The principle is this: “That which has
been propounded by the rishis
[poet-sages], practiced by the sages and appeals to one’s heart should be
followed and put into practice.” The question might arise as to what one is to
do when the thing that appeals to one’s heart is contrary to what has been
propounded by the rishis and practiced by the sages. The answer is, that in such
a case the individual can follow his bent at his own risk. Many reforms and new
discoveries have been made in this way. Our Shankaracharyas
have supported the institution of untouchability but both our head and heart
consider it a blot on Hinduism. We do not care if others consider our belief to
be wrong. (CW, v. 85, p. 53; cf. CW, v. 46, p. 92)
35. CW, v. 66, p. 450.
36. CW, v. 42, p. 73 (“virtue”), CW, v. 74, pp. 75
(“impotent”), 83 (“unmanly”), CW, v. 79, p. 365 (“shortcoming”), HS, p. 44.
37. EW, p. 315. Hind
Swaraj is rife with denunciations of “unmanly,” “emasculated,” and “effeminate”
conduct, and praise for “manhood,” “manliness” and “true men.” It would be
going too far afield to speculate on the roots of his cult of manliness. But
briefly, Hindus (like Jews) suffered the stereotype of physical weakness while
Muslims benefited from the stereotype of physical prowess (CW, v. 71, p. 72,
EW, p. 199). It was therefore perhaps inevitable that a movement of national
revival, even one pledged to nonviolence, would (like Zionism) put an accent on
martial values. One might also note Gandhi’s appropriation of military
metaphors whereby he typically depicted himself as the “general” of an “army of
nonviolence” using “nonviolent arms” (for Gandhi’s praise of aspects of the
military regimen, cf. CW, v. 89, p. 332).
38. CW, v. 85, p. 281 (“impotence”), CW, v. 86, p.
132 (“police”); my emphases.
39. CW, v. 85, p. 235.
40. NR, pp. 132-33.
41. EW, p. 199.
42. CW, v. 61, pp. 265-66.
43. CW, v. 69, pp. 313-16. See also CW, v. 61, p.
316, CW, v. 66, pp. 420, 432, 439, CW, v. 67, pp. 11-12, 437, CW, v. 71, p.
235, CW, v. 74, pp. 92-93, 297-98, CW, v. 82, p. 302, CW, v. 85, pp. 11, 483,
CW, v. 86, pp. 27, 80, 86, CW, v. 87, p. 201.
44. CW, v. 65, p. 361 (“reckless,” “throwing”), CW,
v. 74, p. 28, CW, v. 75, pp. 325-26.
45. CW, v. 66, p. 423, CW, v. 86, p. 89.
46. CW, v. 66, p. 436 (“fearless”), CW, v. 81, p.
438.
47. CW, v. 68, p. 191; but cf. CW, v. 69, pp. 291-92.
48. CW, v. 72, p. 224.
49. CW, v. 66, pp. 436, 449.
50. CW, v. 49, p. 91.
51. CW, v. 89, p. 225.
52. CW, v. 89, p. 129.
53. CW, v. 66, p. 398 (“strongest”), CW, v. 84, p. 12
(“wonderful”), EW, p. 348.
54. CW, v. 43, pp. 268-69 (“bullet”), CW, v. 66, pp.
407 (“emergency”), 447.
55. CW, v. 43, p. 93 (“befall”), CW, v. 66, p. 437
(“smilingly”), CW, v. 67, p. 437 (“cheerfully”).
56. CW, v. 42, p. 397.
57. HS, p. 93.
58. CW, v. 67, p. 422.
59. HS, pp. 94-95. 60. CW, v. 43, p. 297.
61. CW, v. 43, pp. 327-28.
62. CW, v. 84, pp. 399-400; cf. CW, v. 43, p. 339,
CW, v. 49, p. 496, CW, v. 51, p. 381, CW, v. 84, p. 423.
63. CW, v. 50, p. 171.
64. CW, v. 44, pp. 34 (“beneficial”), 164 (“friend”),
325 (“deliverance”), CW, v. 50, pp. 47 (“grand”), 296 (“boon”), CW, v. 87, p.
201.
65. CW, v. 44, pp. 212-13. 66. CW, v. 46, p. 252.
67. CW, v. 46, p. 343.
68. CW, v. 62, pp. 29-30 (“distrustf ul”), CW, v. 63,
p. 59, CW, v. 66, p. 406.
69. NR, p. 154.
70. CW, v. 48, p. 431-35.
CHAPTER THREE
1. For Gandhi’s own delineation of the various forms
of satyagraha, see NR, pp. 214-15.
2. For the points in these paragraphs, see CW, v. 44,
pp. 155-56, 184 (“deprivation”), CW, v. 51, pp. 73 (“ignorance”), 253, 316, CW,
v. 53, pp. 228-30 (“Jesus”), 259 (“Jesus”), CW, v. 55, pp. 410-13, CW, v. 56,
p. 369, CW, v. 72, p. 458, CW, v. 73, pp. 90- 93, 156, CW, v. 80, p. 63, CW, v.
83, pp. 400-1 (“certain”), CW, v. 84, pp. 233-34 (“collections”), CW, v. 86, p.
105 (“duty”), NR, pp. 183, 193, 313-14, 331. For Gandhi’s sexual experiments
with young women, see CW, v. 86, pp. 414, 416, 420, 441-42, 452-53, 465-66,
475-76 (“noncooperation”), and Wolpert, Gandhi’s
Passion, pp. 225-30.
3. CW, v. 48, p. 243.
4. NR, p. 121.
5. CW, v. 74, pp. 164-65.
6. CW, v. 68, p. 30 (“roots”), EW, pp. 260-61, NR,
pp. 131 (“intimidation”), 145. For a slightly bizarre scenario of Gandhi’s, in
which tenants cede to a voracious landlord more of their property than he
actually demands or can use, thereby converting the landlord through
cooperation (ceding the property), noncooperation (refusing to work any of the
land) and love (giving him more than he requests), see CW, v. 72, pp. 226-27.
7. Gandhi also used the locution “passive resistance”
to denote ersatz nonviolence (“nonviolence of the weak”) and distinguish it
from the genuine article.
8. NR, pp. 134-35 (“sufficient”), 155.
9. For Gandhi’s sophistic defense of noncooperation
as noncoercive, see NR, pp. 166-69, EW, p. 335.
10. Although exhorting picketers not to harass
would-be patrons of a liquor store, Gandhi nonetheless granted: “But one is
permitted to cut offrelationship with such individuals by way of [not] going to
their homes for feasts on occasions such as marriages, and indeed one should do
so. In short, they should not be harassed. The pain which they feel when we do
not go to their homes for meals cannot be regarded as harassment” (CW, v. 46,
p. 205). Yet, if not harassment, such ostracism still morally coerced: if the
individuals stop imbibing alcohol, it might simply be to mitigate the pain of
being shunned.
11. CW, v. 78, p. 224, NR, pp. 154 (“claimed”), 222,
229.
12. CW, v. 48, p. 338.
13. CW, v. 43, p. 126 (“touched”), CW, v. 46, p. 105
(“wildest”), CW, v. 51, pp. 167 (“sluggish”), 199 (“people”), CW, v. 55, p. 412
(“awaken”), CW, v. 68, p. 140 (“dignity”), CW, v. 69, p. 70 (“evoke”), CW, v.
78, p. 223 (“stir”), CW, v. 84, p. 372 (“eating”), CW, v. 86, p. 104 (“dead”),
CW, v. 90, p. 202 (“sleeping”), NR, p. 35 (“sympathetic”). Gandhi is not
altogether consistent on which faculty or organ satyagraha appeals to. Besides touching the conscience he speaks
variously of wanting to “appeal ... to the head and the heart,” “appeal to the
heart and soul of the people,” and “touch the hearts” and make an “appeal to
the highest in man,” and “appealing to their reason and to their hearts.” See
CW, v. 43, p. 312, CW, v. 45, p. 222, CW, v. 48, p. 189, CW, v. 54, p. 417, CW,
v. 55, p. 258, CW, v. 56, pp. 197-98, 254, CW, v. 58, p. 159, CW, v. 67, p.
195, CW, v. 78, p. 223, CW, v. 84, p. 372, NR, pp. 178, 181, 191, 202.
14. CW, v. 43, p. 392 (“result”), NR, pp. 77
(“mobilize”), 191.
15. CW, v. 68, p. 20.
16. EW, p. 249.
17. CW, v. 46, p. 313.
18. CW, v. 48, p. 483.
19. NR, p. 213.
20. CW, v. 44, p. 41, CW, v. 48, p. 405, CW, v. 53,
p. 170 (“prejudice”), CW, v. 55, p. 1, CW, v. 79, p. 102, NR, pp. 6, 20, 193.
21. CW, v. 69, p. 212, CW, v. 84, p. 199 (“Nobody”),
NR, p. 193. On a related point, Gandhi acknowledged that, even if mistaken, a
sincerely held opinion cannot easily be dislodged (CW, v. 60, p. 500).
22. HS, p. 91 (“mistakes”), NR, p. 3.
23. EW, p. 357 (my emphasis).
24. In the case of such “personal” fasts, Gandhi set
forth several preconditions for their success: (1) an affective bond must exist
between the wrongdoer and the fasting penitent, otherwise the wrongdoer will
experience the penitent’s fast as “brute force” and “a form of coercion,” not
as born of love; (2) only a person having directly suffered on account of the
wrongdoer can lay claim on a duty and right to do penance; (3) the penitent
must not derive personal benefit from the wrongdoer’s reformation, otherwise it
becomes a species of extortion; (4) the wrongful act for which penance is being
done must be morally unambiguous—“there should be no room for doubt as regards
the fault ... the wrong must be one that is accepted as such by society,”
otherwise it is “not penance but coercion” (CW, v. 50, pp. 193-97). Prima
facie, and without saying more, it might be noticed that a fast by a loved one,
and if only to correct a clear-cut moral failing, might still be experienced by
the wrongdoer as coercive, and if the penitent suffered a direct loss on
account of the wrongdoer’s behavior, then the wrongdoer’s reformation would be
a direct gain for the penitent, and therefore a form of extortion.
CHAPTER FOUR
1. CW, v. 51, p. 118 (“rous[ing],” “duty”), CW, v.
53, p. 164 (“cultivating”), CW, v. 67, p. 350 (“force”).
2. CW, v. 51, p. 62.
3. CW, v. 86, pp. 82 (“bona fides”), 126 (“friend”).
4. The coinage was suggested to Gandhi by
Untouchables, and he adopted it (CW, v. 82, p. 423, CW, v. 83, pp. 36, 365-66).
In current usage, the Untouchables are properly referred to as Dalits.
5. CW, v. 51, pp. 126 (“stealthily”), 342 (“sting”),
344 (“ready”), 386, CW, v. 53, pp. 2, 7, 493 (“whole”). But when one of his
early campaigns against untouchability turned brutal and bloody, Gandhi declared,
“Loss even of a few hundred lives will not be too great a price to pay for the
freedom of the ‘unapproachables.’ Only the martyrs must die clean” (NR, p.
187).
6. CW, v. 43, p. 137.
7. CW, v. 42, p. 373, CW, v. 48, pp. 9, 107, CW, v.
70, pp. 106 (“drink”), 224 (“ripe”), CW, v. 85, pp. 451-52 (“Smoking”).
8. CW, v. 50, p. 289.
9. NR, pp. 189 (“break”), 190 (“hardest”), 197
(“stoniest”).
10. CW, v. 43, p. 220 (“melt”).
11. CW, v. 67, p. 284 (“opprobrium”). In the case of
temple-entry Gandhi was at pains to stress that it was necessary to
“accommodate the minority” opposed to such a reform because “mutual toleration
is the law of the human family” (CW, v. 53, pp. 2-3, 6-8). He proposed granting
Hindu fundamentalists limited hours or spaces of prayer in the temples with no
Untouchables around.
12. CW, v. 80, p. 425.
13. CW, v. 73, pp. 279 (“dreadful”), 336 (“poorest”),
CW, v. 87, p. 452 (“wiped out”).
14. EW, p. 153 (“deliver”), CW, v. 78, p. 251
(“general”).
15. CW, v. 43, p. 148 (“befitting”), CW, v. 44, p.
103 (“classified”), CW, v. 50, p. 213 (“appropriates”), CW, v. 72, p. 399
(“wherewithal”), CW, v. 85, pp. 114-15 (“exploitation”). For Gandhi’s stringent
standard of “non-stealing” (asteya), cf. CW, v. 44, pp. 90-91.
16. CW, v. 72, p. 381.
17. CW, v. 75, p. 158 (“gulf”), EW, p. 86
(“pauperism”).
18. CW, v. 42, pp. 308-9, CW, v. 58, pp. 217-18
(“inherent”), CW, v. 61, p. 183 (“excess”).
19. In fact, Gandhi conceived capitalism as a system
of exploitation and, inasmuch as he opposed exploitation, his ultimate goal was
proximate to that of the traditional Indian Left. Thus he counseled
property-owners who “face the destruction wrought by strikers in their
concerns”:
I would unhesitatingly advise such employers that
they should at once offer the strikers full control of the concern which is as
much the strikers’ as theirs. They will vacate their premises not in a huff but
because it is right, and, to show their goodwill, they would offer the
employees the assistance of their engineers and other skilled staff. The
employers will find in the end that they will lose nothing. Indeed, their right
action will disarm opposition, and they will earn the blessings of their men.
They will have made proper use of their capital. I would not consider such
action as benevolent. It would be an intelligent use by the capitalists of
their resources and honest dealing in regard to the employees whom they would
have converted into honorable partners. (CW, v. 83, p. 309)
See also CW, v. 42, pp. 275-76, CW, v. 58, pp. 29,
247, CW, v. 67, p. 352, CW, v. 86, pp. 413, 423. Gandhi also embraced the
communist ideals of “to each according to his need” and a “classless society,”
and described himself as a “socialist” and a “communist” (CW, v. 45, pp.
298-99, CW, v. 83, pp. 26, 102, CW, v. 84, p. 5, CW, v. 85, pp. 7-8, CW, v. 88,
pp. 261- 63, 282-83; but cf. CW, v. 88, pp. 14-18, 131-32, CW, v. 89, p. 406,
for his occasionally harsh criticism of the tactics of the party-affiliated
Indian Left). On the other hand, he warned, rightly, of the perils of
nationalization by a “soulless” State incarnating “violence in a concentrated
and organized form” (CW, v. 59, pp. 318-20; see also CW, v. 61, p. 183, CW, v.
83, p. 27).
20. See CW, v. 78, p. 248, where a friendly critic of
Gandhi alleges that the support he gets from a well-to-do Indian “prevents
radical reform,” and CW, v. 84, p. 247, where Gandhi defends himself, “Of
course capitalists are among my friends and I take pride in the fact that they
accept me as a friend. But I fight them when I feel there is need and no one fights
them harder. I fought the mill-owners as I suppose nobody had fought them and
successfully.”
21. CW, v. 45, p. 299 (“awaken”), CW, v. 58, pp.
151-52 (“decency”), 218 (“kind,” “ease”), 247 (“squander”), CW, v. 63, p. 404 (“blood-relations”).
22. CW, v. 55, pp. 427-28.
23. See for example CW, v. 69, p. 219:
It may be asked as to how many trustees of this type
one can really find. As a matter of fact, such a question should not arise at
all. It is not directly related to our theory. There may be just one such
trustee or there may be none at all. Why should we worry about it? We should
have the faith that we can, without violence or with so little violence that it
can hardly be called violence, create such a feeling among the rich. We should
act in that faith.
See also CW, v. 45, p. 328, CW, v. 71, p. 28, CW, v.
72, p. 400.
24. CW, v. 45, pp. 339 (“Immediately”), 354
(“demonstrate”), CW, v. 48, p. 418 (“potent”), CW, v. 58, pp. 36 (“necessary”),
75-76 (“necessary”), 121-22 (“self-sacrificing”), CW, v. 59, p. 140, CW, v. 60,
p. 254 (“educated”), CW, v. 67, p. 135, CW, v. 78, pp. 219-21 (“peasant”), CW,
v. 82, p. 267 (“few”).
25. CW, v. 72, p. 401.
26. CW, v. 42, p. 240.
27. Besides opposing class conflict because it
entailed violence, Gandhi also believed that the capitalists possessed
indispensable talents otherwise inaccessible to the working class (CW, v. 45,
p. 339, CW, v. 63, p. 404, CW, v. 72, p. 400, CW, v. 87, p. 284). He somewhat
demagogically dismissed class conflict as a “catchword” and “slogan” that was
“imported from the West” and alien to “Eastern traditions” (CW, v. 58, pp. 219,
248); but cf. CW, v. 62, p. 46, where he qualifies, “The correspondent is wrong
in suggesting that I do not believe in the existence of class struggle. What I
do not believe in is the necessity of fomenting and keeping it up. I entertain
a growing belief that it is perfectly possible to avoid it.”
28. CW, v. 58, p. 29.
29. See CW, v. 42, p. 263, CW, v. 85, pp. 328-29, CW,
v. 87, pp. 451-52, CW, v. 88, pp. 435-37, CW, v. 90, p. 495; but cf. CW, v. 42,
p. 58, where he praises strikes as “a good weapon in the hands of workers for
the removal of genuine grievances.”
30. But see CW, v. 84, pp. 8-9, 102-3, 336, where
Gandhi denounces a sweepers’ strike because it used “coercion.”
31. CW, v. 62, p. 29, CW, v. 67, p. 76 (“dignified,”
“retire”), CW, v. 68, p. 204 (“terrorism”), CW, v. 72, p. 188; but cf. CW, v.
68, pp. 137-41, where Gandhi purports that, if the Poles had disarmed, the
“essential nature” of the invading Nazi and Soviet forces “would have made them
desist from a wholesale slaughter of innocents.”
32. CW, v. 68, p. 204, CW, v. 72, p. 383 (“defeat,”
“zest”), EW, p. 358.
33. CW, v. 62, p. 29, CW, v. 67, p. 415, CW, v. 72,
p. 188 (“Imagine”).
34. CW, v. 48, p. 421 (“corpses”), CW, v. 67, p. 405
(“soul”), CW, v. 68, pp. 204-5 (“annihilated,” “glorious,” “beginning”).
35. CW, v. 72, p. 230, CW, v. 73, p. 322 (“Führer”).
36. CW, v. 68, p. 205.
37. CW, v. 67, p. 405 (“novel”), CW, v. 68, pp. 189
(“fellowfeeling”), 191-92 (“bold”), 277 (“despair”), CW, v. 69, p. 122
(“species”), CW, v. 71, p. 407 (“Nero”), CW, v. 72, pp. 307 (“insane”), 361
(“duped”), CW, v. 73, p. 321 (“debased”), CW, v. 84, p. 420 (“patience”), CW,
v. 86, pp. 156 (“monsters”), 302.
38. CW, v. 68, pp. 139 (“thanksgiving”), 405, CW. v.
69, p. 290 (“guillotine”).
39. CW, v. 68, p. 138.
40. CW, v. 90, p. 522n2.
41. CW, v. 86, p. 100 (“done”), CW, v. 87, p. 200
(“Punjabis”), CW, v. 89, pp. 454-55 (“everybody”).
42. CW, v. 68, p. 139.
43. Arthur Herman, Gandhi and Churchill: The epic rivalry that destroyed an empire and
forged our age (New York: 2008); for Churchill’s loathing of Gandhi and
mockery of his nonviolent resistance, see pp. 509-11, 525; contrariwise, for
Gandhi’s respect for Churchill as a “great man,” see CW, v. 89, p. 254.
44. CW, v. 42, pp. 487-88 (“benefits”), CW, v. 43,
pp. 222-25 (“unmistakable”), CW, v. 86, p. 50 (“entrenched”).
45. CW, v. 60, p. 50.
46. CW, v. 43, p. 7.
47. CW, v. 66, p. 104.
48. EW, p. 197.
49. CW, v. 84, p. 327.
50. CW, v. 48, pp. 168 (“fierce”), 352, 472, CW, v.
66, p. 104 (“notwithstanding”), CW, v. 73, p. 254 (“convert”).
51. CW, v. 42, pp. 209 (“confirmed”), 484
(“destroy”), CW, v. 43, pp. 5-6 (“matching”), CW, v. 48, p. 231 (“obstacle”),
EW, p. 197 (“force of will”).
52. CW, v. 45, p. 311 (“conviction”), CW, v. 48, pp.
435 (“appreciate”; my emphasis), 454.
53. CW, v. 43, p. 6 (“deliberately”), CW, v. 45, pp.
366, 390, CW, v. 48, p. 185, NR, p. 74 (“public opinion”), HS, p. 115. See also
CW, v. 82, p. 155, for Gandhi’s distinction “between the Empire-builder
Englishman of the old type ... and the new type that is now coming into being,
burning to make reparation for what his forefathers did”; but cf. CW, v. 45, p.
267, CW, v. 48, p. 435, CW, v. 79, p. 422, for Gandhi’s verdict that “the
British people have a faculty of self-delusion as no other 100 NOTES people
have,” and his skeptical opinion of “the average man in Europe or America.”
54. CW, v. 43, pp. 179 (“world opinion”), 181, CW, v.
48, p. 397, CW, v. 51, pp. 132-33.
55. CW, v. 87, p. 75 (“quit”), CW, v. 88, p. 302 (“better”).
CONCLUSION
1. Hugh Roberts, “Who Said Qaddafi Had to Go?,” London Review of Books (17 November
2011).
No comments:
Post a Comment